Tesis sobre el tema "Kant, Immanuel, 1724-1804"
Crea una cita precisa en los estilos APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard y otros
Consulte los 50 mejores tesis para su investigación sobre el tema "Kant, Immanuel, 1724-1804".
Junto a cada fuente en la lista de referencias hay un botón "Agregar a la bibliografía". Pulsa este botón, y generaremos automáticamente la referencia bibliográfica para la obra elegida en el estilo de cita que necesites: APA, MLA, Harvard, Vancouver, Chicago, etc.
También puede descargar el texto completo de la publicación académica en formato pdf y leer en línea su resumen siempre que esté disponible en los metadatos.
Explore tesis sobre una amplia variedad de disciplinas y organice su bibliografía correctamente.
Brankel, Jürgen. "Kant et la faculté de juger". Paris ; Budapest ; Torino : l'Harmattan, 2004. http://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb39158082x.
Texto completoCalori, François. "Le sentiment dans la pensée kantienne". Paris 10, 2000. http://www.theses.fr/2000PA100112.
Texto completoFœssel, Michaël. "L' équivoque du monde : l'instance cosmologique dans la philosophie critique de Kant". Rouen, 2002. http://www.theses.fr/2002ROUEL423.
Texto completoThis thesis intends to reveal the emergence , in Kant's philosophy, of a concept of world that is not metaphysical. Starting from the cosmological antinomies, which reveal the world's impossible rationalization, because of its irreducible sensible character, we'll then proceed to the evaluation of this character-an evaluation that has to take into account both the ethical stakes of the world's idea, and the institution of a cosmological view on history and humanity. In the end, we'll try to describe the relation that is established between world and subjectivity, using the concept of membership
Sasseville, Jocelyn. "Définition et rôle du bonheur dans la philosophie pratique d'Emmanuel Kant". Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 1999. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk1/tape9/PQDD_0011/MQ42010.pdf.
Texto completoLonguenesse, Béatrice. "Le pouvoir de juger : sensibilité et discursivité dans l'Analytique transcendentale de Kant". Paris 1, 1992. http://www.theses.fr/1992PA010556.
Texto completoThis book is about the meaning of the forms of judgment as the "leading thread" for the elaboration of the Kantian table of categories. The genesis of the problem of the categories and its solution is followed from the inaugural dissertation in 1770 to the transcendental deduction in 1787. The kantian notion of a logical form of judgment is examined and compared with the definitions of the proposition in the logic text-books of the German schulphilosophie. The reflexive function of the logical forms is emphasized, and it is clarified with the help of the chapter on the amphiboly of concepts of reflection in the critique of pure reason. This reflexive function also brings light to the distinction between judgments of perception and judgments of experience as defined in the prolegomena to any future metaphysics. The doctrine of transcendental imagination and of its synthesis speciosa is then related to the doctrine of the logical forms of judgment. Its leads to a reinterpretation of the transcendental esthetics. It also helps to interpret each of the schema of pure concepts of the understanding, these concepts themselves, and the principles of the possibility of experience which they respectively ground
Peyturaux, Sylvie. "L'interprétation de Dieu comme idéal dans la philosophie de Kant". Paris 4, 2000. http://www.theses.fr/2000PA040138.
Texto completoRogozinski, Jacob. "La question de la loi dans la pensée de Kant". Paris, EHESS, 1993. http://www.theses.fr/1993EHES0307.
Texto completoAfter having examined the interpretations given by hegel and heidegger, we try to describe the genesis of the question of law in kant's work, then its exposition in his practical philosophy, with its equivocities. At last, we consider some marginal parts of his work (historico-political writings, analysis of radical evil and sublime) to try to find a solution to these difficulties
Hjort, Mette. "Art and morality in Kant's Critique of judgement". Thesis, McGill University, 1985. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=63328.
Texto completoMolina, Ureta Javier Felix. "La idea de sistema en el "Opus Postumum" de M. Kant". Doctoral thesis, Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú, 2006. http://tesis.pucp.edu.pe/repositorio/handle/123456789/1311.
Texto completoTesis
Pierobon, Frank S. "La fondation architectonique de la métaphysique dans la critique de la raison pure". Doctoral thesis, Universite Libre de Bruxelles, 1990. http://hdl.handle.net/2013/ULB-DIPOT:oai:dipot.ulb.ac.be:2013/213180.
Texto completoChenet, François-Xavier. "L'Esthétique transcendantale de la "Critique de la Raison pure" de Kant". Université de Provence. Faculté des lettres et sciences humaines (1969-2011), 1987. http://www.theses.fr/1987AIX10050.
Texto completoThe transcendental aesthetic of the "critique of pure reason" presents for kantian studies the problem of its role in the doctrinal organisation of the "critique", and in particular the condordance of its teaching with that of the transcendental analytic. Its presents, in addition, despite its reputation for clarity, a number of difficulties of interpretation, and to this day has continued to arouse numerous objections and reservations, notwithstanding its stated intention of being demonstrative. This is shown conspicuously by the vast quantity of explanatory, justificatory and especially polemical literature to which it has given rise. With its dense text, pregnant with considerable philosophical consequences, the aesthetic therefore requires a meticulous line by line analysis which follows the original text as closely as possible. To understand and evaluate this, it has been necessary to assemble not only the rich academic literature devoted to it, but also the plethora of essays which since 1784 have treated it as a privileged, not to say exclusive, subject. In contrast with those interpretations which see in the aesthetic the vestiges of an outdated state in kant's thought, and which are based notably on his return to the propositions of the "dissertation" of 1770, the originality of his doctrine is stressed here, especially that concerning sensibility and phenomena, its plays an irreplaceable part of the "critique", and it is worth underlining in this respect the inability of cosmological dialectic usefully to replace it. Although it can not completely escape criticism, the aesthetic must be firmly defended against the reproach of beeing incompatible, in letter and in spirit, with the analytic
Delisle, Stéphane. "La notion de progrès dans la philosophie de l'histoire de Kant". Thesis, National Library of Canada = Bibliothèque nationale du Canada, 1998. http://www.collectionscanada.ca/obj/s4/f2/dsk2/tape15/PQDD_0025/MQ26185.pdf.
Texto completoVidal, Las Heras Manuel. "Kant y el simbolismo". Tesis, Universidad de Chile, 2010. http://repositorio.uchile.cl/handle/2250/109939.
Texto completoSoto, Herrera Cristián. "Kant. La imaginación: propuesta para una lectura confusa de la Deducción Trascendental y de otros pasajes de la Crítica de la razón pura". Tesis, Universidad de Chile, 2005. http://www.repositorio.uchile.cl/handle/2250/110275.
Texto completoLa presente investigación consta de partes bien definidas, todas las cuales en lo principal indagan desde una u otra perspectiva o las condiciones en las que la facultad imaginativa surgió dentro de los planteamientos críticos o la naturaleza y el rol que asumió explícitamente en las arquitecturas cognitivas esbozadas en la obra de 1781. Al ser diversos estos esbozos, y al no ser advertida por Kant esta misma diversidad - que tiene notables implicaciones gnoseológicas dentro de la filosofía trascendental -, nuestro propósito será ofrecer un método de lectura confusa que permita llevar a cabo una lectura un poco más clara - más cercana al texto - que la que puede hacerse del mismo sin tener en cuenta las diferencias que observaremos.
Narváez, González Camila. "Hacia una posible disposición metafísica del hombre ante la experiencia : el nóumeno como condición de posibilidad de toda referencia a objetos". Tesis, Universidad de Chile, 2014. http://www.repositorio.uchile.cl/handle/2250/116096.
Texto completoLa mayoría de las veces que se estudia la Crítica de la Razón Pura, las lecturas entabladas se entrampan en la complejidad de momentos como la “Estética Trascendental” o en la intrincada “Deducción Trascendental de las Categorías”, lo que pareciera dejar de lado la importancia del camino que Kant está tomando a lo largo del desarrollo de tal obra. Por ello mismo, se ha llegado muchas veces a la opinión general de la poca consistencia de la visión que el filósofo de Königsberg tenga acerca de asuntos más bien relativos a la aplicación de su teoría del conocimiento a temas de corte metafísico. Por lo mismo, este trabajo recoge una de las punzantes críticas que se han imputado a la filosofía crítica, por la cual se la culpa de amputar todo ámbito de la experiencia al encerrar sus postulados en meras abstracciones. Esto, con el fin de ampliar el punto de vista respecto al cual se pueda hacer una revisión más aclaratoria de lo que significa el nóumeno, en tanto que fundamento de todo aquello cuanto la razón humana sólo puede pensar, pero no conocer. Es decir, abriremos aquí una noción de nóumeno que nos permita comprenderlo como fuente de referencia sobre la cual se podría inspirar toda inclinación metafísica en el sujeto. Será capital, en este sentido,preguntarse por las condiciones de posibilidad de nuestras inevitables aspiraciones metafísicas, lo cual nos exige, quizás, revisar la Crítica de la Razón Pura de maneras poco usuales y, más bien, lejanas a la tradición.
Silva, Sérgio Gomes e. "As noções de Deus, moral e religião e sua função em a religião nos limites da simples razão de Immanuel Kant". reponame:Repositório Institucional da UnB, 2010. http://repositorio.unb.br/handle/10482/8407.
Texto completoSubmitted by Raquel Viana (tempestade_b@hotmail.com) on 2011-06-16T20:13:56Z No. of bitstreams: 1 2010_SergioGomesSilva.pdf: 483868 bytes, checksum: e6768774a2665e504cc99cd8fbaaac91 (MD5)
Approved for entry into archive by Guilherme Lourenço Machado(gui.admin@gmail.com) on 2011-06-17T13:11:22Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 1 2010_SergioGomesSilva.pdf: 483868 bytes, checksum: e6768774a2665e504cc99cd8fbaaac91 (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2011-06-17T13:11:22Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 2010_SergioGomesSilva.pdf: 483868 bytes, checksum: e6768774a2665e504cc99cd8fbaaac91 (MD5)
A dissertação parte da crítica, presente na Crítica da razão pura, à possibilidade da metafísica como ciência. Desta forma, demonstra o questionamento kantiano da concepção de Deus enquanto objeto da teologia racional. A dissertação também problematiza a crítica kantiana à possibilidade da concepção de Deus como objeto metafísico. Além disso, aborda as fronteiras impostas pela crítica à metafísica e, consequentemente, às noções a priori de Deus. Imediatamente chega-se à conclusão de que a noção de Deus encaminha-se para o âmbito prático. No entanto, o problema que o sistema kantiano apresenta é a dedução da lei moral, visto que só a partir dessa dedução é possível identificar a função de Deus na dimensão prática. A dissertação destaca que, na primeira Crítica, a dedução da lei moral é impossível. Por sua vez, na Fundamentação da metafísica dos costumes, essa dedução ainda é metafísica, isto é, a dedução é realizada a partir do conceito negativo de liberdade. Somente na segunda Crítica, por meio do fato da razão, a dedução da lei moral torna-se possível. Estabelecido o âmbito da moralidade, tem-se um terreno apropriado para a religião. Ademais, ressalta-se que Kant pretende analisar Deus e a religião a partir da simples razão. Assim sendo, tanto as noções de Deus como de religião são reinseridos dentro da perspectiva da razão prática pura. A partir desse contexto, depois de ter demonstrado a fragilidade dos argumentos que sustentavam a teologia racional, o filósofo questiona a teologia revelada. Por fim, o filósofo propõe a possibilidade das noções de Deus e de religião sob a perspectiva da teologia moral. _______________________________________________________________________________ ABSTRACT
The thesis starts with the criticism present in the Critique of Pure Reason and it goes through the possibility of having metaphysics as a science. Thus, it demonstrates Kantian issues about the conception of God as an object of rational theology. The research also problematizes the Kantian criticism on the possibility of a conception of God as a metaphysical object. In addition, it discusses the boundaries imposed by criticism on metaphysics and, consequently, the a priori notions of God. Immediately, it is possible to conclude that the concept of God heads for the practical scope. However, the problem that the Kantian system presents is the deduction of the moral law, since, only from such deduction, it is possible to identify the role of God in the practical dimension. The thesis emphasizes that in the first Critique, the deduction of the moral law is impossible. On the other hand, in Groundwork of the Metaphysics of Morals, this deduction is still metaphysical, in other words, the deduction is made from the negative concept of freedom. Only in the second Critique, through the fact of the reason, the deduction of the moral law becomes possible. Having the morality scope established, there is a place for religion. Furthermore, it highlights that Kant intends to analyze God and religion from simple reason. Therefore, both the notions of God as well as of religion are reintegrated into the perspective of Critique of Practical reason. From this context, having demonstrated the frailty of the arguments that supported the rational theology, the philosopher questions the revealed theology. Finally, the philosopher proposes the possibility of notions of God and religion under the perspective of the moral theology.
Ribeiro, Neto João Costa. "Dignidade humana (Menschenwürde) : evolução histórico-filosófica do conceito e de sua interpretação à luz da jurisprudência do Tribunal Constitucional Federal alemão, do Supremo Tribunal Federal e do Tribunal Europeu de Direitos Humanos". reponame:Repositório Institucional da UnB, 2013. http://repositorio.unb.br/handle/10482/12886.
Texto completoSubmitted by Tania Milca Carvalho Malheiros (tania@bce.unb.br) on 2013-04-17T15:32:45Z No. of bitstreams: 1 2013_JoaoCostaRibeiroNeto_Parcial.pdf: 965545 bytes, checksum: dc9e1cd6f189b325fcf4ae5969b9f42a (MD5)
Approved for entry into archive by Jaqueline Ferreira de Souza(jaquefs.braz@gmail.com) on 2013-04-24T13:57:29Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 1 2013_JoaoCostaRibeiroNeto_Parcial.pdf: 965545 bytes, checksum: dc9e1cd6f189b325fcf4ae5969b9f42a (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2013-04-24T13:57:29Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 2013_JoaoCostaRibeiroNeto_Parcial.pdf: 965545 bytes, checksum: dc9e1cd6f189b325fcf4ae5969b9f42a (MD5)
A dignidade humana (Menschenwürde) é um conceito presente em muitas Constituições mundo afora. Este texto tenta identificar o seu conteúdo e extensão, a fim de determinar uma compreensão coerente deste conceito. Ao mesmo tempo, ajuda a evitar que essa ideia setorne uma reserva de equidade (Billigkeitsreserve), ou seja, um conceito vago utilizado pelos juízes para decidir casos difíceis, no sentido que quiserem, de acordo com seus sentimentos pessoais. O Tribunal Constitucional Federal da Alemanha (Bundesverfassungsgericht) tem sido um dos intérpretes mais importantes do conceito de dignidade humana. Não apenas cauisticamente, mas também conceitualmente. Além disso, há bons motivos para acreditar que as origens históricas e filosóficas da dignidade humana, especialmente as que vêm de Immanuel Kant, são ainda importantes para como os doutrinadores e os juízes compreendem essa noção. Nesse sentido, este trabalho está dividido em, basicamente, cinco partes. Primeiro, tenta-se epitomar as origens histórico-filosóficas da dignidade humana até a época de Kant. Em seguida, mostra-se como a ideia é compreendida por juristas, principalmente da Alemanha. Na terceira parte, uma amostra das decisões do Bundesverfassungsgericht é analisada, a fim de mostrar como o Tribunal alemão moldou a noção de dignidade humana. Nas quarta e quinta partes, faz-se o mesmo com as decisões do Supremo Tribunal Federal e do Tribunal Europeu de Direito Humanos, respectivamente. ______________________________________________________________________________ ABSTRACT
Human dignity (Menschenwürde) is a concept present in many Constitutions throughout the world. This text tries to grasp its content and extension, in order to determine a coherent understanding of this concept. At the same time, it helps to prevent this idea from becoming a reserve of equity (Billigkeitsreserve), namely, a vague concept used by judges to decide hard cases in any direction they want, according to their personal feelings. The Federal Constitutional Court of Germany (Bundesverfassungsgericht) has been one of the most important interpreters of the concept of human dignity, not only in a case-to-case basis, but also conceptually. Furthermore, there are very good grounds to believe that the historical and philosophical origins of the human dignity, especially theones that come from Immanuel Kant, are still important to how law scholars and judges perceive this notion. Accordingly, this work is divided in five main parts. First, it attempts to epitomize the historical-philosophical origins of the human dignity up until the time of Kant. Then, it shows how the idea is understood by legal scholars, mainly from Germany. In the third part, a sample of decisions of the Bundesverfassungsgericht is analyzed, in order to show how the Court has shaped the notion of human dignity. In the fourth and fifth parts, the same is done, respectively, to the decisions from the Brazilian Supreme Court (Supremo Tribunal Federal) and the European Court of Human Rights.
Alvarez, Muñoz Teresita. "La Ética del Discurso como reformulación pragmático lingüística de la ética kantianaE". Tesis, Universidad de Chile, 2006. http://repositorio.uchile.cl/handle/2250/110378.
Texto completoRibeiro, Elza Benedita Ferraz. "Um estudo sobre Immanuel Kant : a arte de educar". [s.n.], 2002. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/253403.
Texto completoDissertação (mestrado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Faculdade de Educação
Made available in DSpace on 2018-08-03T04:53:11Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Ribeiro_ElzaBeneditaFerraz_M.pdf: 958158 bytes, checksum: efc11c3f12ad1985c8d1c30a48d38e38 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2002
Mestrado
Maymo, Emirena Giselle Cano. "O círculo de ação em Kant". reponame:Repositório Institucional da UFPR, 2014. http://hdl.handle.net/1884/47726.
Texto completoDissertaçao (mestrado) - Universidade Federal do Paraná, Setor de Ciências Humanas, Programa de Pós-Graduação em Filosofia. Defesa: Curitiba, 07/03/2014
Inclui referências : f. 90-92
Resumo: A cisão que perpassa a filosofia kantiana estabelece uma distância das coisas em si das coisas que o sujeito pode vir a conhecer e, sob esse terreno, a arquitetônica se erige. Essa distância se apresenta na forma sempre limitada do conhecimento em relação ao que é, e a questão desenvolvida visa sinalizar como essa diferença interfere na filosofia prática. Nesse sentido, a divisão sobre a qual trabalhamos não é entre a filosofia teórica e a prática, mas uma passagem possível entre elas a partir da separação entre o que é e o conhecido por um sujeito. Segundo Kant a forma em que o sujeito deve chegar às coisas não é como aluno que se deixa instruir, mas como juiz; sendo o trabalho deste forçar a natureza a responder às perguntas da forma em que são colocadas. Desse modo, é trabalhado no âmbito da filosofia teórica o significado da objetividade de um conhecimento mediado por uma ideia reguladora que o sujeito coloca e sob a qual a experiência é organizada, pois desde essa perspectiva pode ser observada uma realidade que depende de uma forma de olhar o mundo. A problemática que se apresenta na filosofia prática por esse viés depreende-se de que a ética kantiana, mesmo sendo formal, se vê afetada por um limite inerente ao nortear uma ação a partir da universalização de uma máxima que se encontra vinculada a uma ideia e, por tanto, a uma forma de organizar a experiência circunscrita a essa ideia. As consequências que se seguem dessa problemática apontada no liame entre o conhecimento, entendido como constituído a partir de uma experiência regulada, e o ser, como o que se encontra em si além do conhecimento, reside em que a ação do sujeito acontece vinculada a sua compreensão do mundo. Por isso a ética kantiana, mesmo sendo formal, pois visa um ideal que funciona como um horizonte heurístico sob o qual o sujeito finito pode regular seu agir, permite descobrir o espaço para um sujeito ainda não reconhecido como tal na distância entre o conhecer e o ser. Dessa forma o sujeito desconhecido, e portanto invisível, pode se materializar em qualquer "outro" hoje visível, sejam as mulheres, os negros ou os não europeus; mas sem deixar de observar que a filosofia kantiana não tem compromisso com valores estabelecidos, e que o conhecimento é o resultado de uma construção que tem o "homem como seu protagonista último e único responsável." (Alves, 2009: 179) De modo que sob a interpretação apresentada, o sujeito kantiano encontra na incognoscibilidade da coisa em si um limite não ultrapassável que o defronta com a condição de enxergar o mundo através de uma ideia reguladora não, necessariamente, determinante, pois o pensamento que se movimenta dentro de uma estrutura que vá desde um ponto de partida até a projeção de um ato pode vir a questionar o próprio ponto de partida, entendido já como uma construção. Assim, sujeitos ontem invisíveis podem hoje ser vistos, porque mesmo que o limite de uma ideia reguladora nunca esteja ausente, esse limite não se apresenta necessariamente como igual a si mesmo. Ou seja, ao sujeito kantiano é aberta uma possibilidade, não a de escolher sobre o que já está dado, mas sim de questioná-lo e escolher o lugar para o qual quer se dirigir por meio do pensamento autônomo e tomando o conhecimento do dado como um ponto do qual começar. Nesse sentido, é plasmado no trabalho o cenário kantiano, no qual o sujeito protagoniza sua relação com o mundo de forma condicionada por uma ideia que regula a experiência e o conhecimento. A finalidade disso é demonstrar que a partir do conceito de autonomia vinculado à liberdade, encontram-se em Kant as ferramentas para questionar a compreensão da realidade organizada por ideias previamente colocadas que regulam a experiência e, com isso, o sujeito pode dar início a uma ação causal incondicionada. De modo que, se o limite da filosofia kantiana encontra-se na filosofia teórica numa ideia entendida como uma ficção que regula a compreensão do mundo e, na prática, como um arquétipo de ação em decorrência dessa compreensão do mundo, ao mesmo tempo são outorgadas ao sujeito a condição e a responsabilidade de ir além desse limite. Palavras-chave: Conhecimento / Autonomia / Liberdade / Kant
Abstract: The scission that permeates the Kantian philosophy establishes a distance between the things themselves and the knowledge about them and, from this point of view, conceptions are built. In general, the knowledge represents a limited portion of the actual thing and this study intents to demonstrate how this difference affects the practical philosophy. To that extent, the segregation we want to show is not between theoretical and practical philosophy, but the transition among them considering that the things themselves and the knowledge about them are different matters. According to Kant, the way to get to the knowledge is not as a student that allows it to be taught, but as a judge; so the individual has to require the answers to the questions which were done. Therefore, the objectivity is worked under the theoretical philosophy and it's based on a concept that a regulatory idea drives the knowledge which is structured by the individual experiences. From different points of view, the reality could have a different meaning, depending on the individual understanding and experiences. Main point presented by practical philosophy come because Kantian ethics, even been quite formal, is affected by an inherent limit that drives an action from the universalization bounded to an pre-existent idea and, therefore, a way of organizing experience limited to that idea. Based on that, and considering that knowledge, built upon previous regulatedexperiences, and the object itself, that goes beyond its established knowledge, it is a result of an individual action guided by its own comprehension of the life. So Kantian ethics, even though formal, because it seeks an ideal that works as an heuristic horizon that allows to a finite subject adjust his actions during his lifetime, permits to find another unknown subject between knowledge and the actual things. Therefore, a subject never consider as it is can be materialized in any "other" visible today, like women, blacks or non-European, but it is important to consider that Kant's philosophy has no commitment to the established values and for that knowledge is the result based on "the human being as the unique and last responsible protagonist." (Alves, 2009: 179). So, under the interpretation presented Kantian's subject is in the unknowability of the thing in itself an unsurpassable limit that confronts him to the condition of seeing the world through a regulative idea, but not necessarily decisive. Because trough the thought that moves itself within a structure that spans a starting point for the projection of an act can come to question the starting point itself, now understood as a framing. In this way, people that were not visible in the past can be seen today, because even if the boundary of a regulative idea is never absent, it does not necessarily mean that it has to be equal to itself. In other words, it is given to the Kantian's subject a possibility, not to change what is already known, but to make new questions and to choose a new path to go through, as they have an autonomous thought taking the previous knowledge as a starting point. In this sense, the work is shaped following the Kantian's scenario, in which the subject carries out its relationship with the world of limited extent by an idea which governs the experience and knowledge. The purpose of this work is to demonstrate that the tools to challenge the current understanding of these regulatory ideas of the experience can be found in Kant, from the concept of freedom linked to autonomy and thereby initiate an unconditional causal action. So, considering that the limit of Kantian philosophy in his theoretical philosophy is an idea understood as a fiction that governs the human being knowledge, and in his practical philosophy, as an archetype of action due to this understanding of things, at the same time he granted to the individual the condition and the responsibility to go beyond that limit. Key words: Knowledge /Autonomy /Freedom / Kant
Lima, Ítalo Clay Tavares de. "O conceito de dignidade em Kant". reponame:Repositório Institucional da UCS, 2015. https://repositorio.ucs.br/handle/11338/1098.
Texto completoSubmitted by Ana Guimarães Pereira (agpereir@ucs.br) on 2016-01-29T17:21:49Z No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Italo Clay Tavares de Lima.pdf: 1348594 bytes, checksum: 185b01d5ea5d6050386fe9d9233e39bc (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2016-01-29T17:21:49Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Italo Clay Tavares de Lima.pdf: 1348594 bytes, checksum: 185b01d5ea5d6050386fe9d9233e39bc (MD5)
Fundação de Amparo à Pesquisa do Estado do Rio Grande do Sul.
This dissertation aims to analyze the concept of dignity to the Kantian outline. This text begins with the piquiana anthropological concern in conceiving man his place in the cosmos. When Giovani Pico della Mirandola states that the dignity of man emanates from the possibility that he wants to be what you want, and therefore is worthy of admiration, it makes clear the importance of freedom and autonomy for man. Be angel or beast is a genuinely human choice. Henceforth, in Kant the search for elements underlying the dignity of the human person, has as starting point the education of reason toward dignity as it is through education that comes to human dignity, as the act of educating implies humanize. Thinking about education in Kant is related to human behavior (individual) and the moral actions together, as the purpose of education is to order the man before the law and the right so that you can observe justice. Freedom, autonomy and the will are attributes of a properly educated man and knowledgeable of their rights. In addition, the dissertation presents some relations with rousseauian thought in referring to the concept of freedom and human nature. For Kant, the goodness or badness are not aspects determined by the nature. Already Rousseau thinks the act of teaching can be found in the primitive state. Such divergences are widely placed, discussed and analyzed. Clarification (Aufklärung), a leading Kantian concepts, is a turning point for the educational aspect of man as it is in the act to clarify that man happens to make public use of reason. Once cleared, the man begins to exercise his rational nature in order to dignity. There is no doubt that the Kantian thought in general is timeless. Kant became one divider of waters of modernity with an influence on your unquestionable contemporaneity. So what can be concluded on a preliminary basis is the power that education plays in the intellectual and physical training in man. The awareness of merit refers to the fact of being properly educated.
Langlois, Luc. "Kant et le problème de l'histoire". Paris 4, 1991. http://www.theses.fr/1990PA040100.
Texto completoIn the first and second chapter of this work, we try to identify the position of the Kantian philosophy of history in the whole of the critical system. Despite the casual style of Kant’s essays on history, it appears that they play an important role in the resolution of the systematic problem of his philosophy. History is closely linked to the question of a possible articulation between the ultimate end of nature and the practical end of reason. "Is a moral transformation of human freedom possible?" is the question Kant asks in his essays. In the second part (chapt. 3 and 4), we analyze the different factors that influence the progress of human freedom towards its final destination, in taking into account, however, the limits of man's own capacity to integrate his moral end. Ch. 5 is an analysis of the debate between Kant and Herder. Ch. 6 is a short study of the signification of the French revolution in Kant’s philosophy of history
Mavouangui, David. "La philosophie de Kant et l'éducation". Paris 1, 1989. http://www.theses.fr/1989PA010518.
Texto completoThe access to liberty, to moral education (which is the basic task of human education) goes through the recognition of the noumenon ego and the combination of the intelligible and the sensitive world. But though this task is commanded by axiological requirements, it meets the complex natural duality which is found in the human being, finite thinking being who cannot adequately fulfil his intended purpose (slave either of his sensitiveness or of his will) and then reasonable being capable of "good sense", humanity, a supramundane being who is fully involved in the establishment of the ethical city and the intelligible good. The kantian idea of education evolves from this aporetic duality in search of unity and is essentially based upon the critical study of the teleology of the nature on one side and the moral teleology on the other, the principles of political philosophy and that of history, law, religion and culture
Owona, Kisito. "La question de "l'universel" dans la philosophie du droit de Kant : une interprétation africaine". Dijon, 2003. http://www.theses.fr/2003DIJOL027.
Texto completoDrivet, Dario. "La fondation de la physiologie dans l'Opus postumum de Kant". Paris 4, 2002. http://www.theses.fr/2002PA040072.
Texto completoAugusto, Suzete Motta 1948. "Interesse e razão : de Kant a Habermas". [s.n.], 1992. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/279532.
Texto completoDissertação (mestrado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciencias Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-07-14T02:44:12Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Augusto_SuzeteMotta_M.pdf: 23468377 bytes, checksum: a63609a53385f8cc994ce0a0959e81da (MD5) Previous issue date: 1992
Resumo: Não informado
Abstract: Not informed.
Mestrado
Mestre em Filosofia
Keating, Paula School of Philosophy UNSW. "The function of ideas of reason in Kant???s political philosophy". Awarded by:University of New South Wales. School of Philosophy, 2007. http://handle.unsw.edu.au/1959.4/31928.
Texto completoFaggion, Andrea Luisa Bucchile. "O papel do facto da razão na fundamentação da moralidade em Kant". [s.n.], 2003. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/282017.
Texto completoDissertação (mestrado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciencias Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-08-03T15:34:01Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Faggion_AndreaLuisaBucchile_M.pdf: 7017170 bytes, checksum: ed2d13377806dbe0d4ec4d59dd844d48 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2003
Resumo: A fim de analisar o papel que o facto da razão desempenha no problema da fundamentação da moralidade em Kant. a dissertação discute a dedução da fórmula do princípio moral na Fundamentação I e n, pois é importante que se saiba o que estaria para ser fundamentado. Segue-se a análise da suposta fundamentação que Kant ofereceria para tal princípio na m seção da mesma obra. Por fim, lidamos diretamente com a exposição da doutrina do facto da razão, na Critica da Razão Prática, examinando se ela pretende ser uma fundamentação do princípio moral, se teria sucesso enquanto tal e se é ou não compatível com a m seção da Fundamentação, bem como com a idéia de uma filosofia crítica
Abstract: In order to analyse the role that the fact of reason has in the problem of Kant's morality statement, this dissertation first addresses the deduction of the formula of the moral principle in Groundwork I and lI, once it is important to know what is to be stated. Secondly, an analysis of the justification that Kant supposedly would offer for such principle in section m of the same work is made. We finally deal directly with the exposition of the doctrine of the fact of reason, in the Critique of Practical Reason, examining whether it intends to be a foundation of the moral principle, whether it would be sucessful as such and whether it is or not compatible to Groundwork III and to the idea of a critical phi1osophy
Mestrado
Mestre em Filosofia
Boutot, Laurent. "Idéal et normativité dans la philosophie de Kant". Poitiers, 2009. http://theses.edel.univ-poitiers.fr/theses/2009/Boutot-Laurent/2009-Boutot-Laurent-These.pdf.
Texto completoThis study examines the role and the meaning of the concept of the « highest Good » in Kant's practical philosophy. It tries to give a justification for Kant's claim that the highest Good is the necessary and a priori object of pure practical reason, and to give an account for this teleological moment revealed into the « Dialectic of pure practical reason » even though the normative theory founded by the « Analytic » seems to make such a moment useless. At first, the highest Good appears as a necessary object because it refers to the ineluctable and natural striving of reason for the unconditioned. Then, the practical necessity of the highest Good is connected to the fact that this concept, which doesn't belong to the fundamental concepts of ethics, belongs nonetheless to the fundamental concepts of ethic's application to the situation of a finite moral volition. The aspiration to the highest Good is finally related to the moral requirement inherent to practical reason to have an application in the world of nature. For such application is a necessary and a priori duty, the practical task ordering to promote the highest Good inherits of this moral necessity
Castaing, José. "De l'unité du système critique : introduction à la problématique de l'histoire et de la politique dans la philosophie kantienne". Paris 1, 1997. http://www.theses.fr/1997PA010652.
Texto completoThe present work is intented as the test trial of an hypothesis : the unity, in a practical perspective, underlying the theses in the realm of the critical system, belaboured later by Kant in his "practical" philosophy, i. E. The metaphysic of morals, religion within the limits of simple reason, and the political and historical essays. The study of that labour in itself is the object of another research, as distinct from the present. The latter is essentially limited to the "critical system" in order to display in the first part the elements of the practical problem and to elaborate in the second part on the speculative approach through which Kant means to lay the basis of a theory unveiling nature not only as rational and therefore scientifically knowable, but also as originally keyed up to the intelligible destination of man as a limited and reasonable being. The fundamental question, bearing reference to the one in theology, was for Kant to show how in its rationality the world, or creation, was the element of a possible implementation of the law of reason by way of liberty. The study of the difficulties met with in the critiques endeavours to show that the hypothesis of such a pratical/metaphysical avenue of throught leads to establishing the fundamental unity in the system of the three critiques and perhaps to put forward a few interpretive hypotheses. The present work would also (perhaps mainly) lay claim to being a companionable instrument for the reading of the corpus the difficulties of which it is not my intention either to obfuscate or to resolve. Such difficultires are, without much doubt, irretrievably linked to Kant's purpose in producing a philosophy in which faith, if not theology, would at last find its place in a cogent way thanks to the discovery in man of the being through whom might be enacted the finality of the god believed in by Kant; thanks also to the setting out of the conditions under which it is possible to think of man as in charge of such an enactment, and of nature as place for the same
Perez, Daniel Omar 1968. "Kant e o problema da significação". [s.n.], 2002. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/281076.
Texto completoTese (doutorado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciencias Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-07-31T22:15:24Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Perez_DanielOmar_D.pdf: 23253273 bytes, checksum: 25b8d364a554274e1a0272e7ed27b736 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2002
Resumo: Abordaremos a tarefa da filosofia kantiana a partir da pergunta pela possibilidade das proposições sintéticas. Deste modo, indagaremos as operações que permitem a significação dos conceitos usados na formulação de proposições. Isto é, apresentaremos os processos de doação de significação outorgada aos conceitos que constituem os diferentes tipos de proposições possibilitando seu sentido e a formulação adequada de problemas. Seguindo esse fio condutor, estaremos em condições de mostrar que a tarefa kantiana torna-se uma atividade desarticuladora / doadora de sentido, realizando o trabalho crítico contra a metafísica tradicional e elaborando campos semânticos para os diferentes tipos de proposições. Para verificar essa labor precisamos reconstruir os problemas do significado dos conceitos que Kant levanta desde os textos pré-críticos e que só poderá explicar sistematicamente nos textos críticos. Isto nos levará a apresentar dois aspectos dessa atividade como subproblemas: 1 ¿ a preocupação kantiana pelo sistema, isto é, o que significa sistema no texto kantiano no seu duplo aspecto, por um lado, como se desenvolve a questão do sistema da metafísica e, por outro lado, como a crítica é uma atividade sistemática. 2 ¿ a questão de como se estabelece aquilo que existe em relação com os conceitos de cada tipo de proposição, isto é, do que significa existir, não apenas como posição, mas como efetividade dos conceitos ou aquilo ao qual o conceito se refere... Observação: O resumo, na íntegra, poderá ser visualizado no texto completo da tese digital
Abstract: We will broach the task of Kant¿s philosophy from the question of the possibility of the synthetics propositions. In this way, we¿ll wonder about the operations that allow the meaning of the concepts used in the formulation of the propositions. In others words, we¿ll show the procedure of meaning¿s donation that had been given to the concepts that constitute all differents kinds of propositions making possible their meaning and appropriate formulation of problems. It following this way, we will be able to show that the Kant¿s task turn into a dislocate / donor activity of meaning, it making the critical work against the traditional metaphysical and preparing semantics spots to differents kinds of propositions. To check this work out we will need to rebuild the problems of the concept¿s meaning that Kant work out since the precriticals texts and just can be systematically clear in the critical texts. It will make us to show two aspects of this activity as subproblems: 1. the Kant¿s concerns about the system, that is, the meaning of system in the Kant¿s texts in your double aspect, for one side, how is developing the question of metaphysical system and, for other side, how the critic is a systematic activity. 2. the question of how is establishing that wich exists in relation of the concepts in each kind of proposition, that is, what means to exist, not just like position, but like effectiveness of the concepts or that wich the concepts is about... Note: The complete abstract is available with the full electronic digital thesis or dissertations
Doutorado
Doutor em Filosofia
Dieth, Alexis. "Intériorité et moralité chez Emmanuel Kant". Poitiers, 2006. http://www.theses.fr/2006POIT5003.
Texto completoZeni, Alencar Buratto. "Educação e autonomia : uma reflexão a partir da filosofia prática de Immanuel Kant". reponame:Repositório Institucional da UCS, 2010. https://repositorio.ucs.br/handle/11338/503.
Texto completoSubmitted by Marcelo Teixeira (mvteixeira@ucs.br) on 2014-06-02T16:19:47Z No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Alencar Buratto Zeni.pdf: 531236 bytes, checksum: b72cbb0517b4df65d95519fe77604739 (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2014-06-02T16:19:47Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Alencar Buratto Zeni.pdf: 531236 bytes, checksum: b72cbb0517b4df65d95519fe77604739 (MD5)
O objetivo desta dissertação é explicitar o papel que a ação educativa pode desempenhar para que os educandos efetuem a transição da heteronomia para a autonomia, à luz da filosofia de Immanuel Kant. O problema de pesquisa consiste na seguinte questão: quais são as condições e possibilidades de se ter uma ação educativa capaz de promover nos educandos a transição da heteronomia para a autonomia, de acordo com a filosofia de Immanuel Kant? A dissertação está inserida na linha de pesquisa de Filosofia da Educação, no Programa de Pós-Graduação em Educação da Universidade de Caxias do Sul (PPGEd-UCS). Por meio de uma análise interpretativa dos referenciais teóricos, reflete-se, no primeiro capítulo, sobre os aspectos gerais e históricos do Iluminismo, pois fazem parte do ideário iluminista os conceitos de educação e autonomia. Posteriormente, busca-se a aproximação do referido movimento com o pensamento de Immanuel Kant, no intuito de corroborar o entendimento acerca das questõeschave do presente trabalho, utilizando-se, em especial, do texto O que é o Iluminismo? Ao abordar elementos fundamentais da filosofia kantiana e o contexto filosófico no qual se desenvolveu, analisam-se os conceitos de heteronomia e autonomia, utilizando-se como referencial a Fundamentação da metafísica dos costumes. No segundo capítulo, desenvolve-se uma análise interpretativa relativa à educação em Kant, buscando compreender sua concepção pedagógica. Para tanto, utiliza-se como base referencial a obra kantiana intitulada Sobre a pedagogia. No terceiro capítulo, num primeiro momento, elabora-se uma análise interpretativa da importância da filosofia kantiana e das conseqüências da idéia de autonomia na pedagogia contemporânea e, num segundo momento, retomam-se os conceitos de autonomia, heteronomia e educação, procurando explicitar alguns elementos teóricos que permitam refletir sobre as condições e as possibilidades de se ter um processo pedagógico que possa estabelecer uma educação para autonomia. Para tanto, buscou-se referências em autores como, Foucault, Höffe, Piaget e Adorno. É possível educar para a autonomia? No intuito de responder a essa pergunta duas observações são importantes: a) ter presente, como fundamento da consciência dos agentes promotores da educação, a ideia de estabelecer uma ação educativa que prepare o educando para que ele seja capaz de pensar criticamente e de formular os seus próprios juízos, de modo que ele possa decidir como agir nas diferentes circunstâncias da vida; b) refletir sobre a possibilidade da ação educativa para a autonomia, de modo que o professor, por um lado, assuma tal projeto e, por outro, oportunize-o aos alunos a fim de que eles se tornem autônomos.
Cormier, Stéphanie. "L'idéal de la raison dans la Critique de la raison pure d'Emmanuel Kant". Master's thesis, Université Laval, 2006. http://hdl.handle.net/20.500.11794/44088.
Texto completoMeirelles, Agostinho de Freitas. "Critica e historia na filosofia de Kant". [s.n.], 2009. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/280113.
Texto completoTese (doutorado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciencias Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-08-13T05:03:31Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Meirelles_AgostinhodeFreitas_D.pdf: 1015958 bytes, checksum: 5de95c6cae7f4a98ca1b2073d66a1608 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2009
Resumo: Em nossa pesquisa defendemos a tese do projeto de Crítica da razão de Kant (1781-7), no qual, inicialmente, a problemática histórica é abordada de modo pouco elucidativo. O filósofo, segundo nos parece, nunca admitiu a existência de uma ciência histórica, e, por este motivo, jamais pretendeu fundar uma filosofia da história, apesar de o capítulo final da primeira Crítica receber o título de Historia da razão pura, onde Kant menciona a necessidade de examinar a referida história da filosofia segundo a perspectiva transcendental. Motivos não faltarão para duvidar da solidez da Doutrina transcendental do método (segunda parte da primeira Crítica), os quais serão, posteriormente, fornecidos pelo próprio filósofo. No que se refere à segunda Crítica (1788) nenhuma concepção de história se insinua. Em seus textos de filosofia prática escritos após essa obra, os quais abordam, direta ou indiretamente, a questão histórica, não há o apelo à consciência moral do sujeito e muito menos à idéia de uma vontade pura. Estes elementos, constitutivos do domínio da moralidade, são plenamente aceitáveis quando examinada a possibilidade do imperativo categórico. O principal objetivo da filosofia transcendental direcionada para o âmbito moral consiste somente em demonstrar que a lei moral, nos seres finitos, não é uma simples quimera, e que o acatamento subjetivo ao princípio objetivo não é só possível, mas real. Porém, quando a reflexão filosófica kantiana se vê obrigada a responder a respeito da possibilidade de a razão ser efetivamente prática, isto é, provar-se enquanto poder de determinação na natureza humana situada historicamente, o problema a resolver pela filosofia transcendental, como já dissemos, exige outro tipo de análise. Talvez este seja o teste mais difícil enfrentado pela filosofia crítica kantiana. A última centúria de nossa pesquisa visa apontar na terceira Crítica (1790-3) o aplainamento do caminho que facilitará o acesso da filosofia transcendental ao território indemarcável da história. Com a última Crítica, Kant consegue conferir à razão a orientação que necessitava para efetivar definitivamente o Giro copernicano em filosofia
Abstract: In our research we defend the thesis of Kant's Critique of Reason (1781-7), where, initially, the historic issue is approached in an insufficiently elucidative way. The philosopher, in our point of view, never admitted the existence of a historical science, and, for this reason, have never intended to create a philosophy of history, despite the fact that the final chapter of the first Critique is entitled History of pure reason, where Kant mentions the need to examine the aforesaid history of philosophy in conformity with the transcendental perspective. Certainly arguments will arise to bring doubts to the consistency of the transcendental Doctrine of the method (second part of the first Critique), which will, afterwards, be furnished by the philosopher himself. Regarding the second Critique (1788), no conception of history is suggested. His texts about practical philosophy written after the treatise, which approaches, direct or indirectly the historic issue, present no appeal to the moral conscience of the subject and also to the concept of a pure will. These elements, constitutive of the domain of morality, are fully acceptable when the possibility of a categorical imperative is examined. The main objective of transcendental philosophy directed towards the moral scope consists only in the demonstration that the moral law, in the finite existence, is not a simple chimera, and that the subjective acceptance to the objective principle is not only possible, but real. However, when the Kantian philosophic reflection faces the need to given an answer regarding the possibility of the reason being effectively practical, that is, to prove itself as a power of determination in the human nature historically placed, the problem to be solved by transcendental philosophy, as we mentioned before, requires another type of analysis. Perhaps this is the most difficult test faced by Kantian critical philosophy. The last centennial of our research aims to point out in the third Critique (1790-3) the leveling of the pathway, which will make it easier to access the transcendental philosophy to the non-limited territory of history. With the last Critique, Kant was successful in the task to grant to the reason the orientation required to complete the Copernican Revolution in philosophy
Doutorado
Filosofia
Doutor em Filosofia
Ekazama, Richard. "La liberté humaine et la dépendance à l'égard de Dieu chez Kant". Poitiers, 2000. http://www.theses.fr/2000POIT5011.
Texto completoDumouchel, Daniel. "L'approche kantienne du singulier et le problème du jugement réfléchissant : une étude génétique sur la théorie du jugement esthétique et sur son rôle dans la systématique critique". Paris 4, 1992. http://www.theses.fr/1991PA040158.
Texto completoThe object of this study is the development of Kant’s aesthetics and the role they play in the accomplishment of his system of critical philosophy. The first section examines the early development of the aesthetics (1755-1779) with particular regard to the specific philosophical interests influencing each of his pre-critical aesthetic periods: 1 the relation between beauty and finality and their founding in the universe's objective order (1755-1763); 2 the anthropological and ethical founding of aesthetics (1764-1765); 3 the relation between taste and logical common sense (1765-1769) ; 4 the psychological founding of taste in light of Baumgartner’s sensual individuality (1769-1779). Proceeding from this interpretation, the second section attempts a developmental analysis of the critique of judgment. We begin by examining the transcendental founding of the "judgment of taste" as one particular judgment that takes on various forms (taste, natural beauty, the aesthetic idea, the sublime). Further, it becomes apparent that the "critique of taste", developed after 1787, plays a major heuristic role in the accomplishment of the final critique of judgment, and that this original "critique" represents a pivotal juncture around which Kant’s critical thought sought to resolve itself between the years 1787 and 1790
Meirelles, Agostinho de Freitas. "Historia e objetividade em Kant". [s.n.], 2002. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/279544.
Texto completoDissertação (mestrado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciencias Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-08-02T05:51:34Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Meirelles_AgostinhodeFreitas_M.pdf: 11698744 bytes, checksum: 1d870115e36d247ece969a3a5cd04f05 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2002
Resumo: A interpretação da filosofia kantiana a partir de sua Doutrina da objetividade tem como pressuposto, para a determinação do alcance objetivo dos conhecimentos racionais, o prévio exame das condições de possibilidade desses conhecimentos. De modo mais preciso, este exame deve indicar sob que condições são possíveis juízos sintéticos a priori em geral. Para cada domínio de interpretação desses juízos deve existir um procedimento que lhes determine a validade objetiva. Podemos afirmar que a doutrina kantiana da objetividade, seja ela teórica, prática e estético-teleológica, impõe como exigência necessária, para todas as nossas afirmações concementes a esses domínios, a interpretação na sensibilidade. Desse modo, os requisitos lógico-formais não constituem, isoladamente, as condições de possibilidade do conhecimento objetivo. Em nossa Dissertação procuramos estabelecer o nexo entre o conceito de História e Objetividade, diante da necessidade de pensar os juízos históricas como tendo que ser interpretados em um domínio sensível. Pois para a filosofia transcendental kantiana nenhum juízo racional deve permanecer sem dedução
Abstract: Wiht reference to the "Doctrine of Objectivity," the interpretation of Kantian philosophy begins with the assumption that a proper comprehension of the objective basis of racional knowledge requires a prior evaluation of the underlying conditions on which the knowledge is based. More precisely, such an evaluation should indicate under which conditions certain synthetic propositions may be, a priori, interpreted. For each interpretative domain, there should exist a procedure for determining the level of objective validity. One may state that the Kantian doctrine of objectivity, whether theoretical, practical or teleological, estalishes sensitivity as a necessary prerequisite for interpreting propositions contained in each domain. As a result, the logical-formal postulates do not constitute, in themselves, the probable conditions for attaining objetive knowledge. In this dissertation, faced whith the necessity of interpreting historical propositions by recourse to sensitivy, we sougth to elucidate the nature of the nexus existing between "history" and "objectivity". Consequently, in the evaluation of Kantian transcendental philosophy no rational judgement may proceed in the absence of deduction
Mestrado
Mestre em Filosofia
Roullé, Antoine. "La conversion pratique de la métaphysique dans l'oeuvre de Kant". Nantes, 2001. http://www.theses.fr/2001NANT3013.
Texto completoGauthier-Duchesne, Sarah. "Le concept de liberté dans la Critique de la raison pure". Master's thesis, Université Laval, 2018. http://hdl.handle.net/20.500.11794/34863.
Texto completoRodrigues, Niege Pavani [UNESP]. "Kant e a epigênese". Universidade Estadual Paulista (UNESP), 2014. http://hdl.handle.net/11449/123145.
Texto completoCoordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior (CAPES)
A proposta desta dissertação é investigar a filosofia de Kant e sua relação com a teoria da epigênese. Considerando-se as declarações do próprio filósofo feitas no § 81 da Crítica da Faculdade do Juízo, no qual ele defende a teoria da epigênese, considerou-se como valiosa ferramenta analítica avaliar as fontes, relevância e significado que esta relação pode ou deve ter em seu sistema filosófico.
The goal of this dissertation is investigate Kant’s philosophy and his relationship beside the epigenesis theory. Considering his own declarations stand in the § 81 of the Critique of the Power of Judgment, which he defend the epigenesis theory, was considered as a value analytic tool for survey the sources, the relevance and the meaning what this relation can might fill in his philosophical system.
Valeria, Chandía Yanina. "La filosofía del juego en la estética de Immanuel Kant". Tesis, Universidad de Chile, 2004. http://www.repositorio.uchile.cl/handle/2250/110095.
Texto completoEl presente trabajo está destinado a demostrar la hipótesis, de que los planteamientos contenidos en la „Crítica del Juicio‟ acerca de lo bello y lo sublime permiten demostrar que dentro del sistema kantiano opera una „filosofía del juego‟.
Andrade, Renata Cristina Lopes [UNESP]. "Formação moral e educação: um estudo a partir da filosofia prática de Kant". Universidade Estadual Paulista (UNESP), 2013. http://hdl.handle.net/11449/104809.
Texto completoO presente estudo se propõe a explorar e expor a Filosofia Prática de Kant e a sua Doutrina da Educação. Abordaremos o pensamento prático kantiano examinando: i) a sua concepção de moralidade e de educação; ii) a possibilidade, de acordo com o filósofo, da formação moral do educando e do alcance da ética mediante a educação; iii) o exame do ser humano enquanto o ser da liberdade – moral e livre – na filosofia de Kant, ou seja, da educação para o fim ou a destinação da natureza humana. O alcance da ética, isto é, a ação em geral com valor moral, via educação, parece ser possível, segundo Kant, mediante a formação moral do educando, o que envolve a formação do caráter, da pessoa, para a virtude, em valores; o desenvolvimento de um ser humano moral e ético, capaz de mover-se, agir e viver segundo valores e princípios. Desse modo, pretendemos investigar se e compreender como tal concepção de ser humano, de acordo com o pensamento prático kantiano, é possível. Realizaremos uma análise conceitual da filosofia prática kantiana examinando os conceitos e o relacionamento entre eles, fundamentalmente, de moralidade, educação e ética.
This study aims to explore and expose the Practical Philosophy of Kant and his Doctrine of Education. Discuss the practical thinking Kantian, examining: i ) their conception of morality and education , ii) the possibility, according to the philosopher, of the moral education of the student and scope of ethics through education , iii ) the examination of human while the being of the freedom – moral and free - in Kant's philosophy , i.e. , of the education for the purpose or the allocation of human nature . The scope of ethics, that is, the action generally with moral value, through education, seems to be possible, according to Kant, through the moral education of the student, which involves the formation of character, of person, to virtue, in values, the development of a moral and ethical human, able to move, act and live according to values and principles. We intend to investigate whether and to understand how such a conception of human, according to the Kantian practical thinking, it is possible. We will conduct a conceptual analysis of Kantian practical philosophy, examining the concepts and the relationships between them, essentially of: morality, education and ethics.
Gallois, Laurent. "Le souverain bien chez Kant : de l'espérance à l'histoire". Paris 10, 2004. http://www.theses.fr/2004PA100017.
Texto completoThe highest good finds in Kant's philosophy a place which is not strictly limited to the Second Critique. In fact, as soon as it appears in the systematical published works (in the First Critique), the highest good assumes a critical function. This function gives to the concept of highest good a unity and a coherence which are conserved throughout Kant's later philosophy. Moreover, this function helps to read Kant's philosophy as a thought which has nothing to do with an etic of the good intention and (or) rigid formalism. Indeed, Kant does count man's hope as a real matter which concerns reason, and politics as a task to recognize how reason influences the whole life of man and is able to transform the world through liberty with the achievement of the highest good : while history in the shape of a narrative enables to grasp and (re)present its achievement
Bélanger, Annick. "Le problème de la liberté dans la première critique de Kant". Thesis, Université Laval, 2009. http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2009/26349/26349.pdf.
Texto completoWeil, Parodi María Weronika. "¿Cómo es Posible la Belleza? Kant, la Nueva Manera de Pensar en la Estética". Tesis, Universidad de Chile, 2007. http://repositorio.uchile.cl/handle/2250/109008.
Texto completoPrado, Junior Plinio Walder. "De l'art de juger : aspect, affect, écriture". Paris 8, 1998. http://www.theses.fr/1998PA081469.
Texto completoThe context of the present work: that of the collapse of the metaphysical, religious, political certainties and the expansion of the + linguistic turn ; of thought (technologies of language included). What is at stake : to rethink again the power of judgment (from now on without guarantee); reelaborate it again as operation at work by and in the language. Hence the present rereading of wittgenstein, and in particular of his last manuscripts (published under the posthumous title : + philosophy of psychology ;), conducted in the light of the kant of critique of judgement. First task : reconsider the linguistic field itself from a dimension which exceeds its semantic and pragmatic articulations (thus contrary to the anglo-american or german present pragmatics of communication), that is : the dimension of +poetical; work of aspect (in the wittgensteinian sense). It will then be shown that wittgensteinian conception of aspect already contains, in nuce, a philosophy of imagination and judgement (this same judgement that kant calls + reflective ;, and which is not unrelated to the eustochia, the analogical genius that the greeks, opposing it to the episteme, posed as essential as well to poetry as to philosophy). An art of judgement thus emerges, which one already finds at work in the everyday practice of speech (conversation, witticism, lovers' language. . . ), but also in the + complex ; linguistic moods where the fate of an art, a literature, a thought is decided. This implies a thought of writing, sketched here, lastly, from three major motifs : that of the art of interpretation (the freudian deutungskunst), that of the art of aesthetic judgement (the kantian urteilskraft); that of the art of presentation or philosophical style (the darstellungskunst, from the kantian schematism to the wittgensteinian analogic and beyond). (translated by cyd rogers. )
Luna, Málaga Natasha. "Antagonismo e inadecuación : la experiencia de lo sublime según Kant". Bachelor's thesis, Pontificia Universidad Católica del Perú, 2008. http://tesis.pucp.edu.pe/repositorio/handle/123456789/687.
Texto completoBlanc-brude, Gilles. "Psychologie et anthropologie dans la philosophie de Kant". Thesis, Paris 4, 2010. http://www.theses.fr/2010PA040013.
Texto completoKant’s philosophy is not a denial of any form of psychology. Despite the uncertainty of the systematic status concerning the mind’s empirical knowledge and the impossibility to use mathematics to bring this knowledge into the scientific field, despite the vacuity of a deduction about the metaphysical properties of the soul made a priori and the pointlessness of a psychological foundation of both philosophy and logic as well as moral, in brief, despite Kant’s antipsychologism and antinaturalism, themes and psychological issues do remain worthwhile and legitimate in his philosophy. The chapter on “Paralogisms” in the Critique of Pure Reason, associated to the “Refutation of Idealism”, does indeed put an end to the psychologia rationalis -which stems from Wolff’s metaphysics- but yet it makes it possible for psychology to be integrated into anthropology while following the leading thread of experience. Kant’s approach of psychology being intimately related to transcendental philosophy will be both its complement and its illustration through a series of considerations on the genesis of our knowledge, on the connection between interiority and exteriority, the various degrees of consciousness and eventually through considerations on the free use of our mental faculties. The first part will deal with the difficulties to set psychology in relation to Kant’s anthropology and philosophy. The second part will set out the main arguments against empirical and rational psychology. The last part will study Kant’s Anthropology from a Pragmatic Point of View as being the philosophical fulfilment of an untimely theory of the mind complying with the demands of criticism
Aguirre, Silva Marcos. "Imagen, figura y sentido". Tesis, Universidad de Chile, 2010. http://www.repositorio.uchile.cl/handle/2250/101246.
Texto completo