To see the other types of publications on this topic, follow the link: Anscombe.

Journal articles on the topic 'Anscombe'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the top 50 journal articles for your research on the topic 'Anscombe.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Browse journal articles on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.

1

O’Connell, Rory. "“I Do What Happens”: The Productive Character of Practical Knowledge." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 50, no. 5 (2020): 670–86. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/can.2020.12.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractElizabeth Anscombe introduced the notion of “practical knowledge” into contemporary philosophy. Philosophers of action have criticized Anscombe’s negative characterization of such knowledge as “non-observational,” but have recently come to pay more attention to her positive characterization of practical knowledge as “the cause of what it understands.” I argue that two recent Anscombean accounts of practical knowledge, “Formalism” and “Normativism,” each fail to explain the productive character of practical knowledge in a way that secures its status as non-observational. I argue that to
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Lawrence, Gavin. "Reason, Intention, and Choice An essay in Practical Philosophy." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 54 (March 2004): 265–300. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1358246100008547.

Full text
Abstract:
It is the famous first thesis of Anscombe's ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ that we should lay aside moral philosophy—indeed ‘banish ethics totally from our minds’! (p. 38, paragraph 36)—‘until we have an adequate philosophy of psychology’. By a ‘philosophy of psychology’ I understand Anscombe to mean grammatical investigations into various psychological concepts that hold the key to ethics. Anscombe herself instances ‘action’, ‘intention’, ‘pleasure’, ‘wanting’ (‘more will probably turn up if we start with these’). Without such an understanding, she thinks we will simply go astray.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Stockton, Jim, and Benjamin J. B. Lipscomb. "The Anscombe-Lewis Debate: New Archival Sources Considered." Journal of Inklings Studies 11, no. 1 (2021): 35–57. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/ink.2021.0094.

Full text
Abstract:
Meeting from 26 January 1942 through 26 May 1972, the Oxford University Socratic Club was a fixture of Oxford intellectual life for three decades. Founded by Miss Stella Aldwinckle, chaplain to undergraduate women students for the Oxford Pastorate, the club was an immediate success and quickly became a favoured venue for students and faculty alike, with C.S. Lewis serving as club president and senior member (advisor) from its inception to December 1954. One of the club's most famous papers was delivered 2 February 1948, when twenty-eight-year-old Somerville philosopher G.E.M. Anscombe presente
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Ometto, Dawa. "Causality and determination revisited." Synthese 199, no. 5-6 (2021): 14993–5013. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11229-021-03452-6.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractIt seems to be a platitude that there must be a close connection between causality and the laws of nature: the laws somehow cover in general what happens in each specific case of causation. But so-called singularists disagree, and it is often thought that the locus classicus for that kind of dissent is Anscombe's famous Causality & Determination. Moreover, it is often thought that Anscombe's rejection of determinism is premised on singularism. In this paper, I show that this is a mistake: Anscombe is not a singularist, but in fact only objects to a very specific, Humean understandi
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Teichmann, Roger. "The Anscombe-Lewis Debate." Journal of Inklings Studies 1, no. 2 (2011): 55–68. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/ink.2011.1.2.6.

Full text
Abstract:
In Anscombe’s ‘Reply’ to chapter three of Lewis’ Miracles we may discern the influence of her teacher and friend, Wittgenstein, especially in two features of it: (i) Anscombe’s insistence on the variety and diversity of types of explanation, and of senses of ‘because’; (ii) her claim that a person’s reasons for thinking something, or for that matter motives in doing something, are not to be thought of as ‘inner’ processes or events. Lewis argued that an explanation why someone believes that P which alludes to the person’s reasons (grounds) for believing that P must be incompatible with any put
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Beards, Andrew. "Assessing Anscombe." International Philosophical Quarterly 47, no. 1 (2007): 39–57. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/ipq200747157.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Makin, Stephen. "Causality and derivativeness." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 46 (March 2000): 59–71. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1358246100010377.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper is a reflection on some of Elizabeth Anscombe's influential work on causation, in particular on some comments in her Inaugural Lecture at Cambridge, published as ‘Causality and Determination’. One of Anscombe's major concerns in that paper is the relation between causation and necessitation, and she critically discusses the cast of mind which links causality with some kind of necessary connection or with exceptionless generalisation. In place of a semi-technical analysis of causation, Anscombe identifies the obvious and yet little considered core of the causal relation as follows:
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

McCarthy, Christine. "Concrete passions: Anscombe's material politics." Architectural History Aotearoa 8 (January 1, 2011): 20–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.26686/aha.v8i.7097.

Full text
Abstract:
Edmund Anscombe (1874-1948) was an advocate of concrete as a building material, especially in relation to housing. This paper examines Anscombe's promotion of concrete, with specific reference to his patented OK blocks in the 1920s, a time when he is better known for his work on the University of Otago campus, the 1925 New Zealand and South Seas Exhibition, and his move from Dunedin to Wellington in 1928.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Hokari, Toru, and Masayuki Yao. "Eliciting Subjective Probabilities in Anscombe and Aumann's Model." International Journal of Uncertainty, Fuzziness and Knowledge-Based Systems 24, no. 03 (2016): 405–10. http://dx.doi.org/10.1142/s0218488516500203.

Full text
Abstract:
In this note, we propose an alternative version of Anscombe and Aumann's Subjective Expected Utilities (SEU) representation theorem. In Anscombe and Aumann's model, a randomizing device with objective probabilities is available. As pointed out by Sarin and Wakker, when such a randomizing device is available, there is a natural and direct method to elicit subjective probabilities. Anscombe and Aumann did not use this method, but employed an indirect way to derive subjective probabilities. We investigate what happens if we use this direct method to elicit subjective probabilities in Anscombe and
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Connell, Sophia. "Aristotle for the Modern Ethicist." Ancient Philosophy Today 1, no. 2 (2019): 192–214. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/anph.2019.0015.

Full text
Abstract:
Elizabeth Anscombe and Mary Midgley discussed Aristotle's ethics as an alternative to modern moral philosophy. This idea is best known from Anscombe's 1958 paper ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’. The mainstream response has been to design a normative theory of ‘virtue ethics’ to rival deontology and consequentialism. This essay argues that that response is inadequate; it misses Anscombe's point and obscures various aspects of Aristotle's ethics, in particular his emphasis on friendship and human interconnectedness. This element of Aristotelianism was favoured by Midgley. By returning to Midgley, with
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
11

Pigden, Charles. "Anscombe on `Ought'." Philosophical Quarterly 38, no. 150 (1988): 20. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2220265.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
12

Grimi, Elisa. "Anscombe i Wittgenstein." Enrahonar. An international journal of theoretical and practical reason 64 (March 31, 2020): 165. http://dx.doi.org/10.5565/rev/enrahonar.1283.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
13

Estrada Pérez, Luis. "Anscombe y Wittgenstein." Revista Identidad 5, no. 5 (2019): 35–42. http://dx.doi.org/10.46276/rifce.v5i5.592.

Full text
Abstract:
El presente trabajo tiene como objeto mostrar una continuidad entre Wittgenstein y Anscombe, como críticos de la ética ymoral moderna. La primera parte estará dedicada a rastrear la concepción ética y moral de Wittgenstein basándonos enalgunos escritos donde se trabaja esta temática como el Tractatus Logico- Philosophicus, Cultura y Valor; y las Leccionesde Ética. Posteriormente, nos dedicaremos a analizar la crítica de Anscombe a la moral moderna, principalmente en lasegunda tesis de su texto Modern Moral Philosophy y algunos artículos presentes en Ethics, Religion and Politics.Finalmente, ba
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
14

Garrett, Brian. "Anscombe On 'I'." Philosophical Quarterly 47, no. 189 (1997): 507–11. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/1467-9213.00075.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
15

Ortiz-Millán, Gustavo. "José María Torralba, Acción intencional y razonamiento práctico según G.E.M. Anscombe y G.E.M. Anscombe, La filosofía analítica y la espiritualidad del hombre." Crítica (México D. F. En línea) 39, no. 115 (2007): 113–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.22201/iifs.18704905e.2007.514.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
16

Frey, Jennifer A. "Revisiting Modern Moral Philosophy." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 87 (June 2, 2020): 61–83. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1358246119000262.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractThis essay revisits Elizabeth Anscombe's ‘Modern Moral Philosophy' with two goals in mind. The first is to recover and reclaim its radical vision, by setting forth a unified account of its three guiding theses. On the interpretation advanced here, Anscombe's three theses are not independently intelligible; their underlying unity is the perceived necessity of absolute prohibitions for any sound account of practical reason. The second goal is to show that Anscombe allows for a thoroughly unmodern sense of ‘moral' that applies to human actions; the paper concludes with some reasons to thi
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
17

REID, JEREMY. "Virtue, Rule-Following, and Absolute Prohibitions." Journal of the American Philosophical Association 5, no. 1 (2019): 78–97. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/apa.2018.43.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractIn her seminal article ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ (1958) Elizabeth Anscombe argued that we need a new ethics, one that uses virtue terms to generate absolute prohibitions against certain act-types. Leading contemporary virtue ethicists have not taken up Anscombe's challenge in justifying absolute prohibitions and have generally downplayed the role of rule-following in their normative theories. That they have not done so is primarily because contemporary virtue ethicists have focused on what is sufficient for characterizing the deliberation and action of the fully virtuous person, and ru
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
18

Kenny, Anthony. "Elizabeth Anscombe at Oxford." American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 90, no. 2 (2016): 181–89. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/acpq201621176.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
19

McEVOY, James. "Présentation de MmeG.E.M. Anscombe." Revue Philosophique de Louvain 88, no. 2 (1990): 297–301. http://dx.doi.org/10.2143/rpl.88.2.556097.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
20

Cadilha, Susana. "Anscombe llegint a Aristòtil." Enrahonar. An international journal of theoretical and practical reason 64 (March 31, 2020): 63. http://dx.doi.org/10.5565/rev/enrahonar.1276.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
21

Bassols, Alejandro Tomasini. "Anscombe sobre la Sustancia." Tópicos, Revista de Filosofía 21, no. 1 (2013): 103. http://dx.doi.org/10.21555/top.v21i1.318.

Full text
Abstract:
En este artículo reconstruyo la intrincada discusión de Anscombe sobre la noción de sustancia cartesiana. En particular, considero su análisis de la conexión entre cualidades secundarias y lo que sea que a ellas inhiere al tratar de evaluar su conclusión tentativa como algo que no es factible para deshacerse de la noción de sustancia.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
22

Osborne,, Thomas M. "Rethinking Anscombe on Causation." American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 81, no. 1 (2007): 89–107. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/acpq200781149.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
23

O'Grady, Paul. "Anscombe on the Tractatus." Philosophy 71, no. 276 (1996): 297–303. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0031819100041504.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
24

Diamond, Cora. "Disagreements: Anscombe, Geach, Wittgenstein." Philosophical Investigations 38, no. 1-2 (2015): 1–24. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/phin.12074.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
25

Moran, Richard. "Anscombe on ‘Practical Knowledge’." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 55 (September 2004): 43–68. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1358246100008638.

Full text
Abstract:
Among the legacies of Elizabeth Anscombe's 1957 monograph Intention are the introduction of the notion of ‘practical knowledge’ into contemporary philosophical discussion of action, and her claim, pursued throughout the book, that an agent's knowledge of what he is doing is characteristically not based on observation. Each idea by itself has its own obscurities, of course, but my focus here will be on the relation between the two ideas, how it is that the discussion of action may lead us to speak of non-observational knowledge at all, and how this notion can be part of the understanding of a k
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
26

HURLEY, PAUL. "Davidson's Debt to Anscombe." Dialogue 59, no. 2 (2020): 219–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0012217320000050.

Full text
Abstract:
ABSTRACTRobert Myers’ interpretation of Donald Davidson's practical philosophy gets Davidson right in many fundamental respects. Myers rightly argues that Davidson avoids inconsistencies among internalism, ethical objectivity, and the belief-desire theory by modifying central elements of the Humean belief-desire theory, and that Davidson's alternative legitimizes the extension of his interpretation and triangulation arguments into the practical sphere. But at a crucial fork in the interpretive road Myers loses his way. Davidson follows G.E.M. Anscombe down a different path, one that takes indi
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
27

Berti, P., I. Crimaldi, L. Pratelli, and P. Rigo. "An Anscombe-Type Theorem." Journal of Mathematical Sciences 196, no. 1 (2013): 15–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10958-013-1629-6.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
28

Alvarez, Maria, and Aaron Ridley. "The Concept of Moral Obligation: Anscombe contra Korsgaard." Philosophy 82, no. 4 (2007): 543–52. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0031819107000149.

Full text
Abstract:
A number of recent writers have expressed scepticism about the viability of a specifically moral concept of obligation, and some of the considerations offered have been interesting and persuasive. This is a scepticism that has its roots in Nietzsche, even if he is mentioned only rather rarely in the debate. More proximately, the scepticism in question receives seminal expression in Elizabeth Anscombe's 1958 essay, ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’, a piece that is often paid lip-service to, but—like Nietzsche's work—has only rarely been taken seriously by those wishing to defend the conception of obli
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
29

Erbacher, Christian, Anne Dos Santos Reis, and Julia Jung. "“Ludwig Wittgenstein” – A BBC radio talk by Elizabeth Anscombe in May 1953." Nordic Wittgenstein Review 8, no. 1-2 (2019): 225–40. http://dx.doi.org/10.15845/nwr.v8i1-2.3556.

Full text
Abstract:
Presented here is the transcript of a BBC radio broadcast by Elizabeth Anscombe that was recorded in May 1953 – the month when Wittgenstein’s Philosophical Investigations appeared in England for the first time. In her radio talk, Anscombe provides some biographical and philosophical background for reading the Philosophical Investigations. She addresses the importance of the Tractatus and of the literary qualities of Wittgenstein’s writing. Anscombe warns that it would be fruitless to adopt slogans from Wittgenstein without insight. She also calls it a misunderstanding to think that Wittgenstei
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
30

Haldane, John. "A Philosopher of singular style and multiple modes." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 87 (June 2, 2020): 31–60. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s135824612000003x.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractElizabeth Anscombe was one of the most gifted and productive philosophers of the decades following the Second World War. Her writings present challenges to readers: some of them are very difficult to comprehend while others seem philosophically-minded yet situated outside of philosophy as such. There are also the issues of whether she had a philosophical method and of the influence of Wittgenstein on the manner of her approach. A summary and estimate of Anscombe’s enduring contributions is presented before exploring the style and aims of her philosophical work. Then two of her writings
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
31

Belyaev, Max. "METAPHYSICAL IDEAS OF G.E.M. ANSCOMBE." Respublica literaria, no. 1 (December 25, 2020): 71–74. http://dx.doi.org/10.47850/s.2020.1.20.

Full text
Abstract:
The text examines the views of E. Anscombe on the nature of causation. According to the author, the idea of neces-sity should be kept behindthe explanations, but no reference to necessity should be made in relation to the con-nection of events itself. Then certainty will be used in two different contexts: as a characteristic of explanatory judgments (then it is identical with necessity) and as a characteristic of reality (then it has nothing to do with necessity).
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
32

Garret, Brian. "Anscombe and the First Person." Crítica (México D. F. En línea) 26, no. 78 (1994): 97–113. http://dx.doi.org/10.22201/iifs.18704905e.1994.962.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
33

Cavanaugh, T. A. "Anscombe, Thomson, and Double Effect." American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 90, no. 2 (2016): 263–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/acpq201622479.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
34

Stainton, Robert J. "Re-reading Anscombe on ‘I’." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49, no. 1 (2019): 70–93. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2018.1521695.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractAccording to a ‘Straight’ reading of Elizabeth Anscombe’s (1975) ‘The First Person’, she holds a radically non-referring view of ‘I’. Specifically, ‘I’ is analogous to the expletive ‘it’ in ‘It’s raining’. I argue that this is not her conclusion. Her substantive view, rather is that if what you mean by ‘reference’ is a certain rich and recherché notion tracing to Frege, then ‘I’ is not a referring term. Her methodological point is that one shouldn’t be ‘bewitched by language’ into thinking that ‘I’, because of its syntax, must exhibit ‘reference’ in this sense.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
35

Yin, Wenqi. "Anscombe on Sensations of Position." Journal of Human Cognition 4, no. 2 (2020): 4–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.47297/wspjhcwsp2515-469901.20200402.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
36

Aucouturier, Valérie. "Bien agir selon Elizabeth Anscombe." Archives de Philosophie Tome 87, no. 3 (2024): 119–40. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/aphi.873.0119.

Full text
Abstract:
La « vérité pratique », d’après Anscombe, ne vise pas la simple capacité d’agir mais la capacité de bien agir. C’est, écrit Aristote, « la vérité qui s’accorde avec le juste désir ». Anscombe spécifie : « La vérité pratique est la vérité produite par une bonne délibération menant à une décision et à une action, et cela comprend la vérité de la description “bien faire”. » Il s’agit ici de saisir la portée éthique de ce concept qui ne vise pas simplement la structure délibérative de l’action intentionnelle, mais la détermination de ce qu’est une bonne action, et plus exactement une bonne action
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
37

Stout, Rowland. "Practical reasoning and practical knowledge." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 49, no. 4 (2019): 564–79. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2018.1463839.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractThe judgement that provides the content of intention and coincides with the conclusion of practical reasoning is a normative judgement about what to do, and not, as Anscombe and McDowell argue, a factual judgement about what one is doing. Treating the conclusion of practical reasoning as expressing a recommendation rather than a verdict undermines McDowell’s argument; the special nature of practical reasoning does not preclude its conclusions being normative. Anscombe’s and McDowell’s claim that practical self-knowledge is productive of action may be accommodated by identifying the con
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
38

Coope, Christopher Miles. "The Bad News of the Gospel." Philosophy 86, no. 2 (2011): 249–91. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0031819111000064.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractThis article discusses Elizabeth Anscombe's faith and her concept of faith, and the bearing of this on what it is for belief to be reasonable. Reasonableness requires that we make a rough distinction between what can and cannot be taken seriously. At the margin we will rightly be influenced by thinkers such as Anscombe who were well able to appreciate the philosophical consensus but were also prepared to disturb it. She disturbed it in a particular way: by asserting Christian teachings robustly inimical to peace of mind. However she rejected many traditional defences of these teachings
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
39

McCarthy, Christine. "Against ‘Churchianity’: Edmund Anscombe’s Suburban Church Designs." Architectural History 52 (2009): 169–200. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0066622x00004184.

Full text
Abstract:
Edmund Anscombe (1874-1948) was an important New Zealand architect, well known for his design of the 1925 New Zealand and South Seas International Exhibition (Logan Park, Dunedin) and the 1940 New Zealand Centennial Exhibition (Rongotai, Wellington), as well as for his art deco buildings in Hawkes Bay (especially Hastings), and in Wellington.This article explores Anscombe’s contribution to New Zealand’s early twentieth-century church design by presenting new archival research and examining his distinctive use of secular imagery, notably the architectures of the house and schoolhouse. The artic
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
40

Aucouturier, Valérie. "Emotions, intentions and their expressions: Anscombe on Wittgenstein’s stalking cat." Enrahonar. An international journal of theoretical and practical reason 67 (November 30, 2021): 173–97. http://dx.doi.org/10.5565/rev/enrahonar.1286.

Full text
Abstract:
In this paper, I explore the difference between expression of intention and expression of emotion through a discussion of a passage from G.E.M. Anscombe’s Intention, where she claims that expression of intention, unlike expression of emotion, is “purely conventional”. I argue that this claim is grounded on the fact that, although emotions can be described, expressions of emotion are not descriptions at all (e.g. of some present feeling or experience). Similarly, expressions of intention are not descriptions of a present state of mind but are rather the expression of a special sort of foreknowl
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
41

Schadow, Steffi. "Braucht die Moralphilosophie den Begriff der Verpflichtung? Über Anscombes Kritik an der Moralphilosophie der Moderne." Philosophisches Jahrbuch 128, no. 2 (2021): 246–67. http://dx.doi.org/10.5771/0031-8183-2021-2-246.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract. In her much debated article Modern Moral Philosophy Elizabeth Anscombe is known to argue that we are best advised to abandon the concept of moral obligation from moral discourse. This paper offers a step by step analysis of her argument against the concept of moral obligation by considering all of her relevant writings in moral philosophy and action theory. In doing so, it discusses her critical account of morality which turns out to be based on a non-homogeneous theory of practical normativity that has fundamental roots in Modern Moral Philosophy. Finally, it appears that Anscombe’s
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
42

Abakare, Chris O. "The Revival of Virtue Ethics As an Ethical View." PINISI Discretion Review 4, no. 2 (2021): 285. http://dx.doi.org/10.26858/pdr.v4i2.20003.

Full text
Abstract:
Aristotle and Plato were the chief architects of virtue ethics, but their own formulation of virtue ethics was mostly subdued with the appearance of consequentialism as well as Kantian deontology. However, modem thinkers have attempted to revive virtue ethics in its new form and in this regard the name which is popularly known is G.E.M. Anscombe. In fact Anscombe clearly indicates in what sense virtue ethics can be revived and what was wrong with the traditional virtue ethics as expounded by Aristotle and Plato. Anscombe points out three important issues for which traditional virtue ethics per
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
43

Wiseman, Rachael. "Anscombe on Brute Facts and Human Affairs." Royal Institute of Philosophy Supplement 87 (June 2, 2020): 85–99. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1358246119000171.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractIn ‘Modern Moral Philosophy’ Anscombe writes: ‘It is not profitable at present for us to do moral philosophy. It should be laid aside at any rate until we have an adequate philosophy of psychology, in which we are conspicuously lacking’. In consideration of this Anscombe appeals to the relation of ‘brute-relative-to’ which holds between facts and descriptions of human affairs. This paper describes the reorientation in philosophy of action that this relation aims to effect and examines the claim that this reorientation makes possible the sort of philosophy of psychology that can provide
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
44

Haldane, John. "ACPQ Special Issue on Elizabeth Anscombe." American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 90, no. 2 (2016): 171–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/acpq201690283.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
45

Melamed, Noam. "Anscombe i la unitat d’«Intention»." Enrahonar. An international journal of theoretical and practical reason 64 (March 31, 2020): 113. http://dx.doi.org/10.5565/rev/enrahonar.1275.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
46

O'Brien, L. F. "Anscombe and the self-reference rule." Analysis 54, no. 4 (1994): 277–81. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/analys/54.4.277.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
47

CREMASCHI, SERGIO. "ANSCOMBE ON CONSEQUENTIALISM AND ABSOLUTE PROHIBITIONS." DANISH YEARBOOK OF PHILOSOPHY 47, no. 1 (2012): 7–39. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/24689300-90000002.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
48

Cremaschi, Sergio. "ANSCOMBE ON CONSEQUENTIALISM AND ABSOLUTE PROHIBITIONS." Danish Yearbook of Philosophy 47, no. 1 (2012): 7–39. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/24689300_0470102.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
49

Rohrbaugh, Guy. "Anscombe, Zygotes, and Coming-to-be." Noûs 48, no. 4 (2013): 699–717. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/nous.12034.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
50

Bradu, Dan, and Douglas M. Hawkins. "An Anscombe type robust regression statistic." Computational Statistics & Data Analysis 20, no. 4 (1995): 355–86. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0167-9473(94)00048-n.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!