Academic literature on the topic 'Aristotle'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Aristotle.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Journal articles on the topic "Aristotle"

1

Wesoły, Marian. "ΑΝΑΛΥΣΙΣ ΠΕΡΙ ΤΑ ΣΧΗΜΑΤΑ Restoring Aristotle’s Lost Diagrams of the Syllogistic Figures". Peitho. Examina Antiqua, № 1(3) (11 лютого 2013): 83–114. http://dx.doi.org/10.14746/pea.2012.1.4.

Full text
Abstract:
The article examines the relevance of Aristotle’s analysis that concerns the syllogistic figures. On the assumption that Aristotle’s analytics was inspired by the method of geometric analysis, we show how Aristotle used the three terms (letters), when he formulated the three syllogistic figures. So far it has not been appropriately recognized that the three terms — the major, the middle and the minor one — were viewed by Aristotle syntactically and predicatively in the form of diagrams. Many scholars have misunderstood Aristotle in that in the second and third figure the middle term is outside and that in the second figure the major term is next to the middle one, whereas in the third figure it is further from it. By means of diagrams, we have elucidated how this perfectly accords with Aristotle's planar and graphic arrangement. In the light of these diagrams, one can appropriately capture the definition of syllogism as a predicative set of terms. Irrespective of the tricky question concerning the abbreviations that Aristotle himself used with reference to these types of predication, the reconstructed figures allow us better to comprehend the reductions of syllogism to the first figure. We assume that the figures of syllogism are analogous to the figures of categorical predication, i.e., they are specific syntactic and semantic models. Aristotle demanded certain logical and methodological competence within analytics, which reflects his great commitment and contribution to the field.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Chriti, Maria. "A New Direction in Neoplatonic Linguistics: Aristotle as an Adherent of a ‘Specialist Name-Giver’ by Ammonius of Hermeias." Religions 13, no. 2 (February 16, 2022): 172. http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/rel13020172.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper discusses the new linguistic treatment which is formulated for the first time in Neoplatonism, when Ammonius of Hermeias tries to compromise the linguistic views of Plato and Aristotle in his commentary on Aristotle’s On Interpretation. Ammonius integrates doctrines of Plato, Aristotle and Proclus, who was his teacher in Athens. According to Ammonius, Aristotle does not contradict Plato, who believes in the ‘divine name-giver’, the one that attributed the original names to beings; on the contrary, Aristotle confirms what Socrates says in the Cratylus, where he reproaches both his interlocutors for their extreme views. Ammonius examines several aspects of language, capturing Aristotle’s non-adherence to such an extremity. As he wishes to exempt Aristotle from Proclus’ censure, his position does not rest on assumptions, but he goes so far as to investigate Aristotle’s own linguistic behavior. Ammonius manifestly opts for reasoning the reconciliation between Plato and Aristotle, but he is thus led to put the concept of a ‘specialist name-giver’ in Aristotle’s mouth, without clarifying that he is talking about mankind, excluding the divine, although Aristotle never talks about a ‘specialist’, but just about the need to create names, based on the agreement between the members of a linguistic community.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Santoro, Alessio. "A City of Guardians: Refocusing the Aim and Scope of Aristotle’s Critique of Plato’s Republic." Polis: The Journal for Ancient Greek and Roman Political Thought 36, no. 2 (June 28, 2019): 313–35. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/20512996-12340212.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract In Politics 2.2-5 Aristotle criticises the state described in Plato’s Republic. The general consensus in the secondary literature (in particular after E. Bornemann) is that Aristotle’s critique is unfair and too narrow in scope. Aristotle unjustifiably ignores significant parts of Plato’s Republic and unreasonably assumes that the community of wives, children and property extends to the whole of Kallipolis. Although R. Mayhew’s defence of Aristotle’s criticism has mitigated this negative assessment, the problem has remained unresolved. This paper questions the traditional view and suggests an explanation of Aristotle’s selective reading of Plato’s Republic. Based on what turns out to be a reasonable interpretation of Plato’s text, Aristotle does not extend Plato’s communism to the whole city, but rather reduces Plato’s city to the community of the guardians. As a result, Aristotle’s arguments in fact hit the mark and present Aristotle as a much fairer reader than is usually acknowledged.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Johnston, Rebekah. "Aristotle on Wittiness." Epoché: A Journal for the History of Philosophy 24, no. 2 (2020): 323–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/epoche2020226157.

Full text
Abstract:
Aristotle claims, in his Nicomachean Ethics, that in addition to being, for example, just and courageous, and temperate, the virtuous person will also be witty. Very little sustained attention, however, has been devoted to explicating what Aristotle means when he claims that virtuous persons are witty or to justifying the plausibility of the claim that wittiness is a virtue. It becomes especially difficult to see why Aristotle thinks that being witty is a virtue once it becomes clear that Aristotle’s witty person engages in what he calls ‘educated insolence’. Insolence, for Aristotle, is a form of slighting which, as he explains in the Rhetoric, generally causes the person slighted to experience shame and anger. In this paper, I attempt to bring some clarity to Aristotle’s claim that being witty is a virtue by examining why Aristotle thinks that the object of a witty person’s raillery will find this joking pleasant.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Wedin, Michael. "Aristotle on the Impossibility of Anaximander’s apeiron: On Generation and Corruption, 332a20-25." Phronesis 58, no. 1 (2013): 17–31. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/15685284-12341240.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract In On Generation and Corruption, Aristotle rejects the very possibility of such a thing as Anaximander’s apeiron. Characterized as a kind of intermediate stuff, the apeiron turns out to consist of contraries and as such is impossible. Commentators have rightly noted this point and some have also indicated that Aristotle offers an argument of sorts for his negative estimate. However, the argument has received scant attention, and it is fair to say that it remains unclear exactly why Aristotle rejects Anaximander’s intermediate stuff. Indeed, it is unclear how Aristotle’s argument is supposed to run in the first place. This paper offers a reconstruction of Aristotle’s argument for the impossibility of the apeiron, and on this basis offers to explain Aristotle’s grounds for rejecting Anaximander’s intermediate stuff. This is especially called for in light of the fact that Aristotle himself thinks that there can be intermediate stuffs. Finally, some attention is given to the parallel between the apeiron and Aristotle’s prime matter.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Pauw, Francois. "Aristotle’s Poetics in Margaret Doody’s Aristotle and poetic justice." Acta Academica: Critical views on society, culture and politics 42, no. 1 (January 29, 2010): 26–60. https://doi.org/10.38140/aa.v42i1.1236.

Full text
Abstract:
Canadian-born academic Margaret Doody has written several detective novels in which the philosopher Aristotle makes use of his investigative powers to solve murder mysteries. In Aristotle and poetic justice, Stephanos, a friend of Aristotle, narrates how Aristotle solved a double murder which had taken place on the road to Delphi. Doody’s novel provides a convenient framework for a view on the Greek world of 330 BC and, incidentally, a new look at Aristotle’s perception of Greek genres. This article focuses on both these topics, the latter through the lens of Aristotle’s Poetics. In the body of the article, allusions to the Poetics introduced by Doody are examined and evaluated, using a modified version of Genette’s scheme as criterion.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Sembiring, Kharis Samuel. "Ευδαιμονια Kristen dan Pendidikan Teologi Menurut Mazmur 1". ILLUMINATE: Jurnal Teologi dan Pendidikan Kristiani 1, № 1 (30 червня 2018): 59–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.54024/illuminate.v1i1.7.

Full text
Abstract:
Aristotle’s conception of εὺδαιμονια is identical with Psalmist’s (Psalm 1) conception of happiness vizἐνέργεια. According to Aristotle, human’s εὺδαιμονια is ἐνέργεια of the rational element of a human being by its ἀρετη viz. ἀρίστην καὶ τελειοτάτην. Psalmist, on the other hand, shows that happiness is contemplating Torah every moment. In this paper, I will show that we can understand Psalmist’s conception of happiness more accurately by using Aristotelian Ethics. I will then suggest by using Aristotelian reading on Psalm I that Christian Education viz. Theology should pursue εὺδαιμονια as its end.AbstrakKonsep εὺδαιμονια Aristoteles dan kebahagiaan Pemazmur (Mazmur I) memiliki kesamaan pada definisi bahwa εὺδαιμονια dan kebahagiaan adalah sebuah ἐνέργεια. Menurut Aristotle, εὺδαιμονια manusia adalah ἐνέργεια elemen rasional manusia bersesuaian dengan ἀρετη-nya, secara spesifik ἀρίστην καὶ τελειοτάτην. Sementara itu Pemazmur menunjukkan bahwa formulasi kebahagiaan adalah merenungkan Torah sepanjang waktu. Dalam tulisan ini, saya ingin menunjukkan bahwa dengan menggunakan kacamata Etika Aristotle kita bisa memahami konsep kebahagiaan Pemazmur secara lebih mendalam. Melalui pemahaman Mazmur I secara Aristotelian pula saya menyarankan bahwa pendidikan Kristen, secara khusus Teologi harus menjadikan εὺδαιμονια sebagai tujuan akhirnya.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Gerson, Lloyd P. "Platonic Hylomorphism." Rhizomata 10, no. 1 (August 1, 2022): 26–57. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/rhiz-2022-0002.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract Hylomorphism is almost universally claimed to be a staple doctrine of Aristotle. In this paper, I discuss a wide range of texts from the dialogues of Plato that straightforwardly display hylomorphism. Both Plato and Aristotle rest their cognitive realism on their hylomorphism. The crucial difference between Aristotle’s hylomorphism and Plato’s is that Aristotle believes that hylomorphism supports and is supported by essentialism whereas Plato does not. Plotinus presents arguments against Aristotle’s essentialism at the same time as he defends Platonic hylomorphism and his cognitive realism.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Ganson, Todd Stuart. "Aristotle's Metaphysics. Aristotle, Joe Sachs." Isis 92, no. 1 (March 2001): 153–54. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/385074.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Wians, William. "Colloquium 4: Aristotle’s Discovery of First Philosophy." Proceedings of the Boston Area Colloquium in Ancient Philosophy 38, no. 1 (December 11, 2024): 145–66. https://doi.org/10.1163/22134417-00381p11.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract Among the three kinds of theoretical knowledge, Aristotle distinguishes between physics and metaphysics—what he calls Second and First Philosophy. Aristotle’s physics studies changing things, things that change in any of several ways according to an inner principle that governs their alterations and their underlying stability—fundamentally, things that come into being and pass away. What Aristotle calls First Philosophy studies substances that are immovable and unchanging, eternal objects including primarily but not exclusively Aristotle’s god. Aristotle’s distinction between Second and First Philosophy constitutes a decisive difference between Aristotle and earlier philosophers. My main claim will be that Aristotle “discovered” First Philosophy through critical reflection on the universalizing or totalizing assumption of his predecessors. By “universalizing assumption” I mean that according to Aristotle, his predecessors assumed either explicitly or implicitly that they were enquiring into τὸ πᾶν, the all, the totality of everything that exists. Aristotle claims that they were wrong in this assumption. All sciences seek knowledge of principles and causes (archai and aitia). But an investigation of beings that come into existence and pass away is essentially different from the philosophical investigation of immovable, unchanging being. To understand why, one must nevertheless begin by studying changing beings—in large part to come to recognize the insufficiency of Second Philosophy to investigate being as such. Aristotle’s discovery was that the original project of Greek philosophy—the study of the whole—requires both Second and First Philosophy.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
More sources

Dissertations / Theses on the topic "Aristotle"

1

Kwan, Alistair M. "Aristotle on his three elements : a reading of Aristotle's own doctrine /." Connect to thesis, 1999. http://eprints.unimelb.edu.au/archive/00000659.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Müller, Sven. "Naturgemäße Ortsbewegung : Aristoteles' Physik und ihre Rezeption bis Newton." Tübingen Mohr Siebeck, 2006. http://bvbr.bib-bvb.de:8991/F?func=service&docl̲ibrary=BVB01&docn̲umber=015014441&linen̲umber=0001&funcc̲ode=DBR̲ECORDS&servicet̲ype=MEDIA.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Rosler, Andrés. "Political authority and obligation in Aristotle /." Oxford : Clarendon press, 2005. http://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb39905329x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

McConaughey, Zoé. "Aristotle, science and the dialectician's activity : a dialogical approach to Aristotle's logic." Electronic Thesis or Diss., Université de Lille (2018-2021), 2021. https://pepite-depot.univ-lille.fr/ToutIDP/EDSHS/2021/2021LILUH060.pdf.

Full text
Abstract:
Cette thèse développe une analyse formelle de la syllogistique assertorique d’Aristote selon une démarche historiquement et herméneutiquement fondée. Une logique dialogique moderne est proposée dans laquelle les résultats d’Aristote et sa manière d’y arriver sont reproduits,fournissant ainsi une alternative aux approches de la syllogistique fondées sur la déduction naturelle. L’idée principale de cette thèse est que la logique d’Aristote se comprend au mieux avec une approche dialogique. Elle est soutenue par une démarche historique fournissant une interprétation dialogique de sa syllogistique et de sa théorie de l’enquête scientifique, à partir d’une étude de ses textes. Cette interprétation de la syllogistique est ensuite formalisée dans un cadre dialogique, lui fournissant ainsi un soutien supplémentaire<br>This dissertation develops a formal analysis of Aristotle’s assertoric syllogistic that is historicallyand hermeneutically sensitive. It provides a modern dialogical logic that has the same results asAristotle and that develops them in a way akin to Aristotle, providing an alternative to naturaldeduction approaches of syllogistic. The main claim of the dissertation is that Aristotle’s logic is best understood from a dialogicalapproach. It is backed by a historical approach of Aristotle’s texts, providing a dialogicalinterpretation of his syllogistic and theory of scientific inquiry. This interpretation of syllogisticis then formalized in a dialogical framework, thus giving further support to the claim
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Thorsteinsson, Páll Rafnar. "Aristotle on law." Thesis, University of Cambridge, 2011. https://www.repository.cam.ac.uk/handle/1810/252243.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Adams, Rachel R. "Aristotle on mind." Honors in the Major Thesis, University of Central Florida, 2011. http://digital.library.ucf.edu/cdm/ref/collection/ETH/id/9.

Full text
Abstract:
The mind as it is found in Aristotle's great work De Anima is a special capacity of the soul. It has both active and passive properties that work together to allow discursive thinking and moral ethical behavior to emerge. This work will look at Aristotle's philosophy of mind, and I will forward a new interpretation of the mind as he understood it: what I call the active and passive mind property dualism. Aristotle's four causes allow for a unique application of a form of dualism that accounts for the ontological status of the mind and the emergence of rational thinking. The importance of potentiality and actuality in Aristotle's metaphysics gives a different sort of formulation of the mind-body problem than is traditionally understood in the philosophy of mind. The first section of this paper will look at the terms used, especially actuality and potentiality. A comparison to Plato's tripartite soul will be given. Next, Aristotle's different kinds of soul and their varied capacities will be explored. Finally, the active mind will be explained as it appears in Book III, chapter 5.<br>ID: 030476185; System requirements: World Wide Web browser and PDF reader.; Mode of access: World Wide Web.; Accepted in partial fulfillment of the requirements for honors in the major in Philosophy.; Thesis (B.A.)--University of Central Florida, 2011.; Includes bibliographical references (p. 32-34).<br>B.A.<br>Bachelors<br>Arts and Humanities<br>Philosophy
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Pearson, Giles Benjamin. "Aristotle on desire." Thesis, University of Cambridge, 2004. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.615903.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Giulietti, Stephen. "Aristotle on deformities." Theological Research Exchange Network (TREN), 2008. http://www.tren.com/search.cfm?p029-0732.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Journeau, Julie. "Le statut épistémologique de l'éthique comme science pratique selon Aristote." Thesis, Lille 3, 2013. http://www.theses.fr/2013LIL30033.

Full text
Abstract:
Ce travail a pour objet d'interroger le statut épistémologique de l'éthique comme science pratique et d'expliciter l'affirmation d'Aristote selon laquelle l'éthique est une science. Nous abordons cette question en deux temps : le premier est celui d'une confrontation de l'éthique avec les autres savoirs aristotéliciens dans le but de spécifier la catégorie de savoir pratique dégagée en metaph. E. 1, le second est une étude des principales particularités du savoir pratique. Dans le but de déterminer ces différentes particularités, nous revenons sur les obstacles à la scientificité de l'éthique et nous analysons ce que nous considérons être des instruments du savoir pratique : le syllogisme pratique, les endoxa, les portraits et les exemples<br>In this work, I will question the epistemological status of ethics as practical knowledge and I will explain the Aristotelian affirmation that ethics is a science. I will proceed in two axes : the first one is a confrontation of the ethics to the other knowledges in order to specify the nature of the category of practical knowledge brought out in metaph. E. 1, and the second one is a study of main particularities of practical knowledge. In order to specify those particularities, I will define the impediments to ethics' scientificity and I will analyze what I identified as instruments for the elaboration of a practical knowledge : practical syllogism, endoxa, portraits and examples
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Gühler, Janine. "Aristotle on mathematical objects." Thesis, University of St Andrews, 2015. http://hdl.handle.net/10023/6864.

Full text
Abstract:
My thesis is an exposition and defence of Aristotle's philosophy of mathematics. The first part of my thesis is an exposition of Aristotle's cryptic and challenging view on mathematics and is based on remarks scattered all over the corpus aristotelicum. The thesis' central focus is on Aristotle's view on numbers rather than on geometrical figures. In particular, number is understood as a countable plurality and is always a number of something. I show that as a consequence the related concept of counting is based on units. In the second part of my thesis, I verify Aristotle's view on number by applying it to his account of time. Time presents itself as a perfect test case for this project because Aristotle defines time as a kind of number but also considers it as a continuum. Since numbers and continuous things are mutually exclusive this observation seems to lead to an apparent contradiction. I show why a contradiction does not arise when we understand Aristotle properly. In the third part, I argue that the ontological status of mathematical objects, dubbed as materially [hulekos, ÍlekÀc] by Aristotle, can only be defended as an alternative to Platonism if mathematical objects exist potentially enmattered in physical objects. In the fourth part, I compare Aristotle's and Plato's views on how we obtain knowledge of mathematical objects. The fifth part is an extension of my comparison between Aristotle's and Plato's epistemological views to their respective ontological views regarding mathematics. In the last part of my thesis I bring Frege's view on numbers into play and engage with Plato, Aristotle and Frege equally while exploring their ontological commitments to mathematical objects. Specifically, I argue that Frege should not be mistaken for a historical Platonist and that we find surprisingly many similarities between Frege and Aristotle. After having acknowledged commonalities between Aristotle and Frege, I turn to the most significant differences in their views. Finally, I defend Aristotle's abstractionism in mathematics against Frege's counting block argument. This whole project sheds more light on Aristotle's view on mathematical objects and explains why it remains an attractive view in the philosophy of mathematics.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
More sources

Books on the topic "Aristotle"

1

Williams, Brian. Aristotle. Chicago: Heinemann Library, 2002.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Shields, C. Aristotle. New York, USA: Routledge Philosophers, 2007.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Steve, Parker. Aristotle. London: Belitha, 2003.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Losev, Alekseĭ Fedorovich. Aristotle. Moscow: Progress Publishers, 1990.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

1940-, Dunn John, and Harris Ian 1963-, eds. Aristotle. Cheltenham, UK: Edward Elgar Pub., 1997.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

George, Klosko, ed. Aristotle. Burlington, VT: Ashgate Pub., 2007.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

McLeish, Kenneth. Aristotle. New York: Routledge, 1999.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

George, Klosko, ed. Aristotle. Aldershot, Hampshire: Ashgate Pub., 2007.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Cope, Edward Meredith, and John Edwin Sandys, eds. Aristotle: Rhetoric. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/cbo9780511707421.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Aristotle: Aristotle's Poetics. London: Phoenix, 1998.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
More sources

Book chapters on the topic "Aristotle"

1

Daniel, Drew. "Lynx-Eyed Aristotle." In Speculative Medievalisms, 173–78. Brooklyn, NY: punctum books, 2013. https://doi.org/10.21983/p3.0021.1.16.

Full text
Abstract:
And now for some catty remarks. In the Prologue to the Expo-sitio super viii (octo) libros Physicorum, William of Ockham pounces upon a particularly jarring image with which to praise Aristotle’s exceptional status among the philosophers:The most accomplished man to have appeared among them is Aristotle, outstanding as a man of no slight or insignificant learning. With the eyes of a lynx, as it were, he explored the deep secrets of nature and re-vealed to posterity the hidden truths of natural philos-ophy.1I’m placing this image of the lynx-eyed Aristotle beside Kellie Robertson’s learned and capacious essay because Ockham’s queer construction of a nocturnal, feline Aristotle further supplements her archive of medieval Aristotles: the infidel, the physicist, the S&amp;M bottom engaged in a brisk session of pony-play with a rampant Phyllis, but more importantly, the thinker of a hylomorphic metaphysics whose enduring alterity might help to pry us out of present predicaments. Joining this company, scenting the air with paws extended and pupils di-lated wide, Ockham’s lynx-eyed Aristotle stands poised to forage for what lies hidden within the dark world of physical nature that Graham Harman’s project has plumbed so fierce-ly. Since Kellie’s paper is both historical in its exposition of the past archive of these medieval Aristotles and proleptic in its sense of how that history might reinforce and prepare the way for Graham’s own paper today, I want to cut left and simply flag some key, portable points in Kellie’s paper that I found most generative. These points—hers not mine—potentially help to anchor a particularly life-saving rope bridge that we might throw across some wide gaps in philosophical history.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Simpson, Peter L. P. "Aristotle." In A Companion to Ancient Greek Government, 105–18. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd., 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781118303214.ch7.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Thorp, John. "Aristotle." In Sourcebook in the History of Philosophy of Language, 73–106. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-26908-5_4.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Herrmann, Douglas J., and Roger Chaffin. "Aristotle." In Recent Research in Psychology, 56–74. New York, NY: Springer New York, 1988. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4612-3858-4_9.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Michalos, Alex C. "Aristotle." In Encyclopedia of Quality of Life and Well-Being Research, 225–29. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-0753-5_3940.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Deer Richardson, Linda, and Benjamin Goldberg. "Aristotle." In History, Philosophy and Theory of the Life Sciences, 49–59. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-69336-1_6.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Hetherington, Norriss S. "Aristotle." In Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers, 103–6. New York, NY: Springer New York, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4419-9917-7_72.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Strobach, Nico. "Aristotle." In The Moment of Change, 47–83. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1998. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-015-9127-0_3.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Aydüz, Salim, Leonard B. Abbey, Thomas R. Williams, Wayne Orchiston, Hüseyin Topdemir, Christof A. Plicht, Margherita Hack, et al. "Aristotle." In The Biographical Encyclopedia of Astronomers, 60–62. New York, NY: Springer New York, 2007. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-0-387-30400-7_72.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Lennox, James G. "Aristotle." In Ancient Philosophy, 361–408. First [edition]. | New York : Routledge, 2017.: Routledge, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315179339-11.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Conference papers on the topic "Aristotle"

1

Ade, Dr Rajesh Anandrao. "The Poetics of Aristotle: An Introduction." In Two Day National Interdisciplinary Conference on Script Writing, 79–81. Bhavnagar, Gujarat, India: SK Publisher, 2024. https://doi.org/10.61165/sk.publisher.script.writing.2024.17.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Ballal, Dr M. B. "Aristotle’s Poetics." In Two Day National Interdisciplinary Conference on Script Writing, 127–30. Bhavnagar, Gujarat, India: SK Publisher, 2024. https://doi.org/10.61165/sk.publisher.script.writing.2024.26.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Ingle, Nagesh Wasudeo. "The Architecture of Tragedy: Analyzing Aristotle's Six Components in the Poetics." In Two Day National Interdisciplinary Conference on Script Writing, 44–48. Bhavnagar, Gujarat, India: SK Publisher, 2024. https://doi.org/10.61165/sk.publisher.script.writing.2024.10.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Di Maio, Francesco, Nicola Pedroni, Matteo Taroni, and Enrico Zio. "ARtificial Intelligence and STOchasTic Simulation for the rEsiLience of Critical InfrastructurES (ARISTOTELES)." In 2024 8th International Conference on System Reliability and Safety (ICSRS), 482–86. IEEE, 2024. https://doi.org/10.1109/icsrs63046.2024.10927422.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Yilmaz, Deniz, linghai lu, Marilena Pavel, Michael Jump, and Michael Jones. "Comparison of Simulator Platform and Flight Tasks on Adverse Rotorcraft Pilot Coupling Prediction." In Vertical Flight Society 70th Annual Forum & Technology Display, 1–17. The Vertical Flight Society, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.4050/f-0070-2014-9576.

Full text
Abstract:
Previous investigators have found that obtaining the same results using different simulation facilities for notionally identical test can be difficult to achieve. This was also found to be true in the EC-Framework 7-funded ARISTOTEL project. This project used two simulators in parallel - the HELIFLIGHT-R Simulator (HFR) at the University of Liverpool and SIMONA Research Simulator (SRS) at TU Delft in a study aimed at creating tools and techniques to predict, detect and eliminate rotorcraft pilot couplings (RPCs). Therefore, an essential part of the investigation was to understand the effect of using these two simulator platforms on the ability of pilots to detect rotorcraft pilot couplings (RPC). Similarity between the two facilities was verified both objectively and subjectively for three key simulation components: the open-loop aircraft flight dynamics model, the visual display system and the motion drive system. The closed-loop pilot-awarded subjective visual and motion cueing ratings indicated that the two simulators had reached a good level of similarity for the latter two of these items. Inspection of non-linear responses to pre-defined control inputs showed the same for the aircraft model. Pilot-in-the-loop flight simulation test campaigns were conducted on four ADS-33E-PRF maneuvers: Acceleration-Deceleration, Vertical Maneuver, Hover Maneuver, and Roll Step. The data obtained was analyzed in terms of subjective Handling Qualities Ratings and Pilot-Induced-Oscillation Susceptibility Ratings and objectively using the pilot cutoff frequency. It was found that the ratings obtained using SRS were generally higher than the corresponding data from HFR. An explanation for this finding was provided by using a modified time-varying power frequency metric to distinguish pilot control activities in the frequency domain between the two simulators. Pilots in SRS generally have higher stick activity intensity than when flying in HFR. The subjective and quantitative results show that SRS appears to provide a more RPC-susceptible environment than HFR and this appears to be due to its slightly lower resolution visual environment when compared to HFR.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Danilova, Valeriia Iurevna. "The Problem of the Best Constitution in Aristotle's "Politics"." In International Scientific and Practical Conference. TSNS Interaktiv Plus, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.21661/r-508651.

Full text
Abstract:
In the paper the proper constitutions of Aristotle's "Politics" are compared. The author concludes that Aristotle preferred aristocracy and polity which are much alike. Being a realist Aristotle knew that aristocracy and polity were rear in practice and not suitable for all the nations.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Harrold, Mary Jean, Loren Larsen, John Lloyd, David Nedved, Melanie Page, Gregg Rothermel, Manvinder Singh, and Michael Smith. "Aristotle." In the 33rd annual. New York, New York, USA: ACM Press, 1995. http://dx.doi.org/10.1145/1122018.1122038.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Knepper, Richard, Susan Mehringer, Adam Brazier, Brandon Barker, and Resa Reynolds. "Red Cloud and Aristotle." In HARC '19: Enabling and Facilitating Research on Cloud Computing. New York, NY, USA: ACM, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1145/3355738.3355755.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Rayside, Derek, and Gerard T. Campbell. "Aristotle and object-oriented programming." In the thirty-first SIGCSE technical symposium. New York, New York, USA: ACM Press, 2000. http://dx.doi.org/10.1145/330908.331862.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

SOHN, Yunrak. "Civic Education and Communication in Aristotle." In 8th International Conference On Humanities, Psychology and Social Science. ACAVENT, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.33422/8hps.2018.10.120.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Reports on the topic "Aristotle"

1

Kovacevic, Emina. Increasing Student Performance and Building Self-esteem through Diverse Literature Choices: Using Saenz’s Aristotle and Dante Discover the Secrets of the Universe. Ames (Iowa): Iowa State University, May 2023. http://dx.doi.org/10.31274/cc-20240624-892.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Hills, Thomas, Gus O'Donnell, Andrew Oswald, Eugenio Proto, and Daniel Sgroi. Understanding Happiness: A CAGE Policy Report. Edited by Karen Brandon. The Social Market Foundation, January 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.31273/978-1-910683-21-7.

Full text
Abstract:
Everyone wants to be happy. Over the ages, tracts of the ancient moral philosophers – Plato, Aristotle, Confucius – have probed the question of happiness. The stirring words in the preamble to the Declaration of Independence that established ‘Life, Liberty and the pursuit of Happiness’ as ‘unalienable Rights’ served as the inspiration that launched a nation, the United States of America. Yet, more than 240 years later, the relationship between government’s objectives and human happiness is not straightforward, even over the matters of whether it can and should be a government aim. We approach this question not as philosophers, but as social scientists seeking to understand happiness through data. Our work in these pages is intended to enhance understanding of how the well-being of individuals and societies is affected by myriad forces, among them: income, inflation, governance, genes, inflation, inequality, bereavement, biology, aspirations, unemployment, recession, economic growth, life expectancies, infant mortality, war and conflict, family and social networks, and mental and physical health and health care. Our report suggests the ways in which this information might be brought to bear to rethink traditional aims and definitions of socioeconomic progress, and to create a better – and, yes, happier – world. We explain what the data say to us: our times demand new approaches. Foreword by Richard Easterlin; Introduced by Diane Coyle.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Zulkarnain, Iskandar. TEORI KEADILAN : “PENGARUH PEMIKIRAN ETIKA ARISTOTELES KEPADA SISTEM ETIKA IBN MISKAWAIH”. Jurnal Madani: Ilmu Pengetahuan, Teknologi, dan Humaniora, March 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.33753/madani.v2i1.37.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Hagensick, Michael. A Comparative Study of Aristotle's Poetics and Ezra Pound's ABC of Reading. Portland State University Library, January 2000. http://dx.doi.org/10.15760/etd.2256.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Tyson, Paul. Climate Change Mitigation and Human Flourishing: Recovering Teleology, Avoiding Tyranny. Mέta | Centre for Postcapitalist Civilisation, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.55405/mwp5.

Full text
Abstract:
It is most unlikely that adjusting to a 1.5 to 2 degree hotter world is possible within the prevailing political and economic norms of our times. In our post-capitalist times we need to modify modern technological market “liberalism” (which has become, actually, techno-feudalism). If we do not modify our present norms, the collapse of the natural means of power and privilege native to our present world order makes it almost inevitable that democratic liberalism will devolve further into a distinctly anti-liberal species of techno-tyranny. To avoid such a dystopian future, this paper explores how we might re-imagine our global politico-economic norms without embracing techno-tyranny. The argument put forward is that modern liberalism makes the means of personal wealth accumulation and private freedom, the end of public life. This confusion of means with ends implies, ironically, that if our means become unviable, we have no way of aiming at valuable human ends by different means. We have a culturally assumed faulty teleology in political economics and in our philosophy of technology. A revised form of Aristotle’s teleology is proposed whereby an understanding of common human flourishing defines human ends, and where a range of new means could then be pursued to achieve that end, respecting the natural limitations on means that are now upon us.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Aristotle, Ethics and the ‘Art’ of Leadership. IEDP Ideas for Leaders, September 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.13007/202.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!