Dissertations / Theses on the topic 'Aristotle. Matter'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the top 15 dissertations / theses for your research on the topic 'Aristotle. Matter.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Browse dissertations / theses on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.
Kwan, Alistair M. "Aristotle on his three elements : a reading of Aristotle's own doctrine /." Connect to thesis, 1999. http://eprints.unimelb.edu.au/archive/00000659.
Full textShatalov, Keren. "Aristotle's Subject Matter." The Ohio State University, 2019. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=osu1554224731153183.
Full textCrowley, Timothy James. "Aristotle on the matter of the elements." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2009. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:e4b90312-72a2-404a-909c-f1cc4761b31e.
Full textEbrey, David Buckley. "Aristotle's motivation for matter." Diss., Restricted to subscribing institutions, 2007. http://proquest.umi.com/pqdweb?did=1467889261&sid=1&Fmt=2&clientId=1564&RQT=309&VName=PQD.
Full textAinsworth, Thomas Ross. "The grounds of unity : substantial and sub-substantial being in Aristotle." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2013. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:c5dbc768-4fee-4528-9522-c6cff2204c99.
Full textKyriakidis, Vasileios G. "John the Grammarian's objections to Aristotle on the eternity of the world a critical re-examination /." Theological Research Exchange Network (TREN), 1999. http://www.tren.com.
Full textMassobrio, Simona Emilia. "Aristotelian matter as understood by St. Thomas Aquinas and John Duns Scotus." Thesis, McGill University, 1991. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=39263.
Full textSeminara, Simone Giuseppe. "Matter and Explanation. On Aristotle's Metaphysics Book H." Phd thesis, Ecole normale supérieure de lyon - ENS LYON, 2014. http://tel.archives-ouvertes.fr/tel-01061421.
Full textVoogd, Stephanie Wilhelmina de. "The Matter of form : three conversations /." [S.l.] : S. de Voogd, 1986. http://catalogue.bnf.fr/ark:/12148/cb35018753q.
Full textMichaud, Myriam. "L'acte de philosopher en Philosophie pour enfants." Thesis, Université Laval, 2010. http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2010/27431/27431.pdf.
Full textChung, Hyun Sok. "Enjeu anthropologique de l’union de l’âme et du corps chez Bonaventure et Thomas d’Aquin : anima est forma corporis substantialis." Thesis, Paris 4, 2010. http://www.theses.fr/2010PA040101.
Full textThe objective of this thesis is to understand how 13th century thinkers have adopted the famous dictum of Aristotle's De anima II that “the soul is the first act of the organic body potentially having life”. In this perspective, this thesis examines the way in which Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas, each with his own creativity, elaborated to establish the unity of human being that consist in their claim that the human soul and body are not two distinct substances, but two essential parts of the human nature or a human person. In so doing, this thesis analyses the concepts like “substance”, “hoc aliquid”, “intellective soul” “intellect” etc and their meaning in respective contexts where Bonaventure and Thomas Aquinas give us relevant solutions that can deal with problems arising from the "two substances view", or substance dualism
Kwan, Alistair Marcus. "Aristotle on his three elements: a reading of Aristotle's own doctrine." 1999. http://repository.unimelb.edu.au/10187/2858.
Full textMore particularly, the thesis defends three main points:
Firstly, Aristotle’s discussion of pre-Socratic and Plato’s philosophies of nature reveals a commitment to finding elements in the sense of the most fundamental things knowable. These elements apply to not just matter, but to the whole of nature. The evidence for Aristotle’s commitment to absolute fundamentals is in his word usage: he speaks of the various kinds of elements (roots, first principles, etc.) as absolute fundamentals, and uses the terms interchangeably. The evidence for his interest in nature (rather than only matter) is found within his argument, where the assumptions give away his motives.
Secondly, since Aristotle considers nature to be, as he puts it, a principle of change, his elements turn out to be his familiar three elements of change: form, privation, and substratum. While change is the focus of this framework, the approach allows matter to be analysed, leading Aristotle to a substantial substratum underneath each change. Thus, he confirms the existence of the four simple bodies (earth, water, air and fire), and deduces, from the premise that they change, that there is another substratum beneath them.
And thirdly, since this substratum underneath the four simple bodies is known only by deduction, Aristotle cannot sense its features, and his three-element framework is powerless to analyse it any further. That last substratum is therefore at the edge of his knowledge, and in a purely epistemic sense, it is featureless and prime.
This epistemically prime matter is of no great importance to Aristotle - its primality is not even important enough to warrant extended discussion, and he certainly leaves the way open for further analysis, if ever that substratum turns out to suffer sensible change. In the hands of scholars focussed on the elements of matter, this last knowable substratum was perhaps the inspiration behind the traditional prime matter.
Many recent works deny Aristotle’s support for traditional prime matter. There is a danger that refutations of traditional prime matter refute also my epistemically prime matter, and thus attack the heart of this thesis. However, because they focus on matter rather than on change and nature more generally, those refutations in fact prove harmless, their analysis indeed often agreeing with mine in the course of their discussion.
Nathan, Usha Manaithunai. "Aristotle's Pathē: Why they Matter." Thesis, 2021. https://doi.org/10.7916/d8-gsb9-t458.
Full textChik, Janice T. "The unity of action: reviving a neo-Aristotelian case for hylomorphism." Thesis, 2009. http://hdl.handle.net/2152/ETD-UT-2009-05-123.
Full texttext
Drouin-Léger, Phillip. "La lecture aristotélicienne du non-être chez Platon : le platonisme comme une pensée de l’être en puissance." Thèse, 2019. http://hdl.handle.net/1866/23451.
Full textIt has often been said that Aristotle’s philosophy represents an overturning of Platonism. Yet, a close reading of the second chapter of Book N of the Metaphysics reveals that we call an overturning might be closer to a surpassing. This thesis will explore this surpassing from a specific point of view, that of potential being. Indeed, in the aforementioned second chapter of Book N, Aristotle criticizes Platonists for having believed that all beings would form a single one if they did not refute Parmenides’ argument against the being of non-being. Aristotle then situates the Platonists’ fundamental mistake as having argued that non-being in some way « is ». However, Plato did not need to make non-being « be » he simply needed to think the multiplicity of ways which being can be said. Only then would he have found the principle of multiplicity that he wanted : potential being (dunamei on). Hence, having failed to notice that being is said in many ways, he could never think « matter » through properly. This, according to Aristotle, condemns Plato to a thought of potential being and material being. In order to argue for this position, we will firstly establish the importance of the Sophist in the platonic project, for as we have said, Aristotle places the Platonist mistake squarely in this dialogue. Secondly, we will need to show how Aristotle’s concept of non-being is central to his conception of potential being. We will do this by offering a close reading of the relevant passages of Book Q of the Metaphysics. Having established in the first chapter that Plato does indeed integrate non-being into being in the Sophist and in the second that Aristotle considers being penetrated by non- being to be merely potential being, we can read N.2 with more precise knowledge of the platonic « error » and in turn liberate Aristotle’s conception of non-being from Plato’s ; the topic of our third chapter. Finally, in our fourth chapter we will show why platonic conceptions of matter can never be adequate for Aristotle and explore the consequences of not having properly distinguished actual being from potential being, namely all of Plato’s principles are merely potential principles and not actual ones. Hence, we can conclude that for Aristotle, Plato’s ideas and principles of being are composite potential beings, close to mere possibilities.