Academic literature on the topic 'Fortune Ethics'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Fortune Ethics.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Journal articles on the topic "Fortune Ethics"
Bowlin, John. "Contingency and Fortune in Aquinas's Ethics." Pro Ecclesia: A Journal of Catholic and Evangelical Theology 11, no. 1 (February 2002): 111–13. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/106385120201100113.
Full textKohls, John, Christi Chapman, and Casey Mathieu. "Ethics Training Programs In the Fortune 500." Business and Professional Ethics Journal 8, no. 2 (1989): 55–72. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/bpej19898210.
Full textYilmaz, Sevdiye E., and Emine Cetinel. "Ethics Projections in Vision and Mission: Fortune 500 the Case of Turkey." International Business Research 9, no. 5 (March 16, 2016): 25. http://dx.doi.org/10.5539/ibr.v9n5p25.
Full textJohnson, Kent. "Luck and Good Fortune in the Eudemian Ethics." Ancient Philosophy 17, no. 1 (1997): 85–102. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/ancientphil19971715.
Full textBretzke, James T. "Book Review: Contingency and Fortune in Aquinas's Ethics." Theological Studies 62, no. 1 (February 2001): 181–83. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/004056390106200126.
Full textJohnson, Mark. "Contingency and Fortune in Aquinas’s Ethics by John Bowlin." Thomist: A Speculative Quarterly Review 65, no. 3 (2001): 492–96. http://dx.doi.org/10.1353/tho.2001.0010.
Full textSpillman, Monique A., and Robert Sade. "Does Fortune Foul Fidelity?" American Journal of Bioethics 11, no. 9 (September 2011): 14–15. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/15265161.2011.593688.
Full textBarros, Paula. "In Fortune Fair and Foul." Critical Survey 32, no. 3 (September 1, 2020): 82–93. http://dx.doi.org/10.3167/cs.2020.320308.
Full textHolcomb, John, Hugh Grove, and Maclyn Clouse. "Does the existence of ethics and compliance committees improve stock market and financial performance?" Corporate Board role duties and composition 15, no. 1 (2019): 8–16. http://dx.doi.org/10.22495/cbv15i1art1.
Full textValdecantos, Antonio. "Between Ethics and Poetics (Responsibility, fortune and uncertainty according to Aristotle)." Enrahonar. Quaderns de filosofia 30 (July 7, 1999): 99. http://dx.doi.org/10.5565/rev/enrahonar.420.
Full textDissertations / Theses on the topic "Fortune Ethics"
Dean, Brian Edward. "The problem of moral luck the indeterminacy of moral responsibility and the instability of moral judgment /." Theological Research Exchange Network (TREN), 1998. http://www.tren.com.
Full textBarry, Nicholas. "Defending luck egalitarianism /." Connect to this title, 2006. http://theses.library.uwa.edu.au/adt-WU2007.0036.
Full textShew, Melissa M. 1977. "The phenomenon of chance in ancient Greek thought." Thesis, University of Oregon, 2008. http://hdl.handle.net/1794/8545.
Full textThis dissertation engages three facets of Greek philosophy: (1) the phenomenon of tyche (chance, fortune, happening, or luck) in Aristotle's Physics, Nicomachean Ethics , and Poetics ; (2) how tyche informs Socrates' own philosophical practice in the Platonic dialogues; and (3) how engaging tyche in these Greek texts challenges established interpretations of Greek thought in contemporary scholarship and discussion. I argue that the complex status of tych e in Aristotle's texts, when combined with its appearance in the Platonic dialogues and the framework of Greek myth and poetry ( poiesis ), underscores the seriousness with which the Greeks consider the role of chance in human life. I claim that Aristotle's and Plato's texts offer important counterpoints to subsequent Western philosophers who deny the importance and existence of chance in human affairs and in the universe, dichotomously privileging reason over fortune (Boethius), necessity over chance (Spinoza), certainty over contingency (Descartes), and character over luck (Kant). My investigation of tyche unfolds in relation to a host of important Greek words and ideas that are engaged and transformed in Western philosophical discourse: anank e (necessity), aitia (cause, or explanation), automaton, logos (speech), poietic possibility, and philosophy. First, a close reading of tyche in the Physics shows that its emergence in Book II challenges the "four causes" as they are traditionally understood to be the foundation of the cosmos for Aristotle. Attentiveness to the language of strangeness (that which is atopos ) and wonderment ( t o thauma ) that couches Aristotle's consideration of tyche unveils a dialogical character in Aristotle's text. I also show how tyche hinges together the Physics and the Nicomachean Ethics . Second, I argue that tyche illuminates the possibility of human good through an inquiry into human nature in the Ethics , exploring the tension that tych e is, paradoxically, a necessity as it is grounded in nature and yet relates to human beings in "being good" ( EN 1179a20), ultimately returning to a deeper understanding of the relation between physis and tyche . Third, I argue that the Poetics also sustains an engagement with tyche insofar as poi esis speaks to human possibility, turning to Heidegger and Kristeva to see how this is so.
Adviser: Peter Warnek
Neeves, Peter M. "Performance Implications of Fortune 500 Companies' Self-Interest in Corporate Social Responsibility Activities." ScholarWorks, 2015. https://scholarworks.waldenu.edu/dissertations/2674.
Full textWalfard, Adrien. "Tragédie, morale et politique dans l’Europe moderne : le cas César." Thesis, Paris 4, 2011. http://www.theses.fr/2011PA040110.
Full textThis dissertation investigates the functions of moral and political thought in modern tragedy (16th-18th centuries), focusing on a group of Neo-Latin, French, Italian and English plays which represent the death of the Roman dictator Julius Caesar, as well as on Corneille’s Cinna. In order to provoke the tragic emotions, a fable must represent a character or a group of characters whose fall from happiness into mishap is a consequence of a morally or politically ambiguous “flaw”. This sequence is particularly tragic when the “flaw” is at least partially unintentional and results from a kind of necessity : tragedy thus manifests the importance of “moral luck”. The ambiguity of the tragic “flaw” may arise from different circumstances ; in the plays representing the death of Caesar it consists on the one hand in the antinomies which the characters must face, on the other hand in the fact that their motivations appear in some ways contrary to the arguments they use in order to justify themselves. Modern tragedy is profoundly extraneous to contemporary casuistry (as developed in the rhetorical theory of invention, in moral and political philosophy and in historical writing), in that it leaves moral and political “cases” unsolved. However, Cinna, the first happy-ending tragedy in the French theatre, shows how reconciliation and a morally and politically satisfying ending are possible despite the tragic antinomies
Barry, Nicholas. "Defending luck egalitarianism." University of Western Australia. School of Social and Cultural Studies, 2007. http://theses.library.uwa.edu.au/adt-WU2007.0036.
Full textGreene, Sonia Marlene. "Barriers Encountered by African American Women Executives in Fortune 500 Companies." ScholarWorks, 2019. https://scholarworks.waldenu.edu/dissertations/7475.
Full textDias, Verônica Ferreira. "A construção da realidade - o estudo do processo criativo de Eduardo Coutinho na elaboração do documentário Santo Forte." Universidade de São Paulo, 2010. http://www.teses.usp.br/teses/disponiveis/27/27153/tde-23052013-104519/.
Full textThe aim of this thesis is to compare and analyze the unedited material with the commercial movie Santo forte to identify - by means of studying the documentary completion process, the selections and articulations of images and testimonials - the authorial trace of Eduardo Coutinho, his methodology (interview based) and his ethics (both directed to the \"social actor\", in order to preserve a person\'s image and the image of the character created, and to the \"spectator\", in order to explain in the movie itself the way it has been constructed). When selecting the participants for his movies, Coutinho takes into account the ability one has to fairly tell their stories - ability that will allow him to create interesting characters. On the one hand, if participants should \"act fittingly\" for the camera, on the other, it is Coutinho´s responsibility to stimulate this performance. To accomplish this, the movie maker uses some strategies for the interviews: starts the interview naturally, dealing with general themes or talking about subjects that he may have in common with the participant; he stays physically close to the interlocutor, he does not follow a script of questions, thus allowing the participant to speak freely; he looks for the appropriate time to resume the issues that he thinks are most interesting; he has the support of people on the staff who have had previous contact with the participant; he does not skip a question asked by the interviewed person and does not enter into confrontation with him.
Filho, Dinaldo Sepúlveda Almendra. ""A firma é forte": trabalho, crime e consumo nas redes de sociabilidade da "violência urbana"." Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro, 2013. http://www.bdtd.uerj.br/tde_busca/arquivo.php?codArquivo=6367.
Full textEsta tese argumenta que aquilo que Alba Zaluar chamou de ética do provedor, quer dizer, a prática em torno da qual o trabalhador pobre urbano e favelado construía a sua identidade em relação à do bandido, sofreu uma metamorfose, cujo resultado foi a emergência de uma ordem de interação sui generis inscrita nas redes de sociabilidade da violência urbana. A ética do provedor metamorfoseou-se em uma lealdade instrumental e isso deu origem a uma espécie de vínculo social armado e impulsionado internamente como uma forma de convívio capaz de forçar as relações de rotina em dois movimentos concomitantes, de aproximação e de separação de quem vive e circula nessas redes de sociabilidade da violência urbana. O estudo da forma de convívio é feito a partir da construção de uma coleção de relatos baseada em entrevistas com um grupo heterogêneo de tipos sociais por exemplo, trabalhador favelado, ex-traficante, familiar de bandido, policial militar, policial civil, militar das Forças Armadas, jornalista, fotógrafo, professor da rede pública, pesquisador, militante de Direitos Humanos, advogado etc. , e, também, da observação flutuante em três favelas, uma delas com tráfico de drogas a varejo armado e ostensivo e as outras duas com Unidades de Polícia Pacificadora (UPPs). Assim, a coleção de relatos e a observação flutuante são articuladas num recorte transversal e não linear orientado para a abordagem dessa ordem de interação emergida por contiguidade entre a ordem social convencional e a violenta, visando capturar a dimensão intersubjetiva e empírica da forma de convívio que junta e separa, simultaneamente, as pessoas que vivem sob ameaça da violência física, do assédio moral e da corrupção do dinheiro, fatores altamente coercitivos e que produzem os deslizamentos de sentido entre as categorias crime, trabalho e consumo.
This thesis argues that the frontiers that are used to separate the identification at slum communities of a poor urban worker from a bandit, in its classical sense, have been blurred. It results in the hypothesis that the transformation of the ethics of the provider (former anchorage point of separation between worker and bandit), into instrumental loyalty has given origin to some sort of social link to an interaction order sui generis that is armed and driven from inside by an interpersonal companionship provision capable of forcing the every-day relationships towards two simultaneous movements: approximation and separation of the social types who have free pass because of the proximity between the life routines of law and order and that of violent social order. This interaction order sui generis is studied through a) building of a collection of reports based on open interviews with a group of social types radically heterogeneous such as poor urban worker, military and civil police, Armed Forces former military, former drug dealer, lawyer, journalist, photographer, professor of the public network, researcher, activist of Human Rights, etc.; and b) floating observation of routine situations at a slum with ostensive and armed drug dealing and two others slums with non-ostensive drug dealing and Police Pacification Units ( UPPs Unidades de Polícia Pacificadora), in search of verifying the effects of instrumental loyalty on theses relations networks. The collection of reports and the floating observation are operated in a transversal and nonlinear cut, capable of encompassing not only diversity, but above all, the intersection of the points of view created for each of them from the worlds and reference framework to which they belong. They are all affected to some extent by some coercive factors resulting from the violent common crime, to wit: the open or implicit threat of physical violence, corruption, and moral harassment, practical and symbolic factors that spins the meaning of categories as crime, work and consumption.
Carvalho, Tiago Mesquita. "A medida e as coisas. Virtudes, responsabilidade e tecnologia." Doctoral thesis, 2019. http://hdl.handle.net/10451/43876.
Full textThis thesis provides a virtue ethics approach for building a conceptual framework that allows one to think of a rationale for action vis-à-vis technology in the context of the current environmental crisis. Our research acknowledges and departs from the observation that the multiplicity and rhythm of technological innovation already demands an appropriate ethical consideration in vast areas of human life. Nevertheless, such changes also announce a challenge for the reflective exercise of ethics itself. The thesis comprises five parts. The first part presents the main concepts of Aristotelian ethics. Individual moral progress is conceived through the role of the virtues and a teleological conception of human nature. The distinction between the intellectual virtues of theory, techne and phronesis is established through their role in affording and assisting moral progress. These concepts are in turn critically recovered and extended by Alasdair MacIntyre to contemporary ethical thought through the apologetic understanding of the superiority of Aristotelian ethics. To this author and in spite of various constraints that overshadow moral agency, action still and should retain a rationality rooted in the biological roots of the human species, its frailty, exposure to fortune and a teleology secondary to a socially defined good. The second part stems from the insufficiency of the previously presented concepts to account for technology in its own terms. There are several conceptual absences: 1) the disregard of technology in the way it alters the ends of action in praxis; 2) the structuring of human nature and of moral progress by technology itself through the wider exteriority of nature. These elements should in turn be complemented by the notion that the historical process of Modernity largely corresponds to the erosion of the Aristotelian framework. Briefly, this process consisted 1) in the fruitful alliance between theory and techne to provide humanity with the use and convenience of nature through scientific and technological progress; 2) in the ruin of teleology in nature and in moral progress; 3) in the avoidance of the ability of phronesis to determine the ultimate good; 4) and in the equivalence between the laws governing society and the ones governing nature, on the assumption of the feasibility of an optimization. Just as Alasdair MacIntyre criticize Modernity for the failure of its attempt to rationally justify morality, we will also assess the greater meaning of the separation between facts and values and the close related assumption that scientific knowledge, through technology, is sufficient for moral progress, a notion that constitutes the keystone of several modern utopias. Among other authors, the central role of this second part belongs to Hans Jonas. His oeuvre not only complements the referred conceptual absences about human nature, but above all he questions the essentially pre-modern positioning of ethics in relation to technology. Through the examination of his main theses we can start accounting for a critical proposal that takes into account the consequences of technology itself for ethical reflexivity and an argument that echoes the difference between techne and phronesis about the difference between scientific and technological progress and moral progress. In its formal dynamics, modern technology is characterized by the magnitude, scale and irreversibility of its effects. These features lead to the establishment of an epistemological gap between the power to do and the power to forecast in relation to that same doing. Shortly, that is, to a dissociation between moral agency and the consequences of its action. This condition, called techno-opacity, is remedied by Hans Jonas through the heuristics of fear, through which the moral imagination attempts to establish realistic future scenarios that safeguard the unpredictability of technological action. The third and fourth parts launch us directly into the contemporary debate in philosophy of technology. Generally, limits are settled regarding the comprehensiveness of the formal dynamic’s description of technology as an autonomous force to whose laws of motion humanity is necessarily bound in compliance. It is through the analysis of the substantial content of technologies, i.e., how concrete technologies are instantiated in relationships with agents, that one can understand how perception and action are modified and how moral agency can still be fulfilled according to the orientation of the good life. On the whole, the third part thus concerns the confrontation of authors whose common heritage goes back to the work of Heidegger. Through the revelation-occultation structure of technology common to Don Ihde, Albert Borgmann and mediation theory, we will revisit concepts advanced by Hans Jonas, specifying how moral agency is conditioned by materiality and, contrary to Bruno Latour, what is the fundamental difference between moral responsibility and causal responsibility. Through an Aristotelian reading of Albert Borgmann's work, we will observe how his device paradigm and the notion of focal things and practices allow us to overcome the epistemological gap. We consider that his work is to some extent a recovery vis-à-vis technology of flourishment, according to objective criteria of human nature. The fourth part essentially deals with the work of Ivan Illich. The novelty of this author relates to his analysis of various divisions and institutions of industrial society as being essentially counterproductive, that is, undermining the pursuit of the objectives for which they were designed. Illich reads industrialization as a current chapter in the history of religion. The ecclesiology of industrial society largely neglects the search for the goods internal to vernacular practices, favoring the ecumenical distribution of services and commodities that are plagued by scarcity. The neo-Aristotelian alternative for Illich is the cultivation of ascetic practices through which convivial technologies can participate in human flowering by realizing the finiteness of human nature and its social, material and natural roots. In the last part we intend to apply the developed framework of conceptual resources to a case study. We will examine the possibility of establishing a food ethics in the context of the current industrial food system in which technology is widely present. The act of eating should account for the epistemological gap that crosses food production. Eating should be a matter of deliberation according to the conception of a good that favors human flourishment in its material, social and environmental components.
Books on the topic "Fortune Ethics"
Contingency and fortune in Aquinas's ethics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1999.
Find full textSeel, Martin. Versuch über die Form des Glücks: Studien zur Ethik. Frankfurt am Main: Suhrkamp, 1995.
Find full textO'Neill, A. Nicole C. Psychic secrets!: What is your psychic gift? : and how to use it properly. Canoga Park, CA: ALS Publications, 2009.
Find full textO'Neill, A. Nicole C. Psychic secrets!: What is your psychic gift? : and how to use it properly. Canoga Park, CA: ALS Publications, 2009.
Find full textMorality, moral luck, and responsibility: Fortune's web. New York: Palgrave Macmillan, 2005.
Find full textill, Lanan Jessica, ed. Good fortune in a wrapping cloth. Walnut Creek, CA: Shen's Books, 2011.
Find full textScaramucci, Anthony. Goodbye Gordon Gekko: How to find your fortune without losing your soul. Hoboken, N.J: Wiley, 2010.
Find full textGunther, Marc. Faith and fortune: The quiet revolution to reform American business. New York: Crown Business, 2004.
Find full textBuddensiek, Friedemann. Die Theorie des Glücks in Aristoteles' Eudemischer Ethik / Friedemann Buddensiek ; [verantwortliche Herausgeber: Dorothea Frede und Günther Patzig]. Göttingen: Vandenhoeck & Ruprecht, 1999.
Find full textLeiber, Theodor. Glück, Moral und Liebe: Perspektiven der Lebenskunst. Würzburg: Königshausen & Neumann, 2006.
Find full textBook chapters on the topic "Fortune Ethics"
Mitchell, J. Allan. "On Fortune, Philosophy, and Fidelity to the Event." In Ethics and Eventfulness in Middle English Literature, 11–26. New York: Palgrave Macmillan US, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/9780230620728_2.
Full textSpiegelberg, Herbert. "Good Fortune Obligates: Albert Schweitzer’s Second Ethical Principle." In Steppingstones Toward an Ethics for Fellow Existers, 219–29. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1986. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-009-4337-7_12.
Full textWeaver, Gary R., Linda Klebe Treviño, and Philip L. Cochran. "Corporate Ethics Practices in the Mid-1990s: An Empirical Study of the Fortune 1000." In Citation Classics from the Journal of Business Ethics, 625–40. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2012. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-4126-3_31.
Full textPetriccione, Matteo. "Il fantasma di Alatiel: desiderio, parola e memoria in Decameron II 7." In Intorno a Boccaccio / Boccaccio e dintorni 2019, 37–51. Florence: Firenze University Press, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.36253/978-88-5518-236-2.03.
Full textMitchell, J. Allan. "Telling Fortunes in Lydgate’s Fall of Princes." In Ethics and Eventfulness in Middle English Literature, 87–109. New York: Palgrave Macmillan US, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/9780230620728_6.
Full text"11. Good Fortune." In Aristotle's Ethics, 197–202. Princeton University Press, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/9781400852369-012.
Full text"The fortune of the good life and the scandalous resemblance between happiness and fortune." In Ethics of Hospitality, 57–73. New York : Routledge, 2017. | Series: Law and politics: continental perspectives: Routledge, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315618241-5.
Full text"Eudemian Ethics." In Aristotle's Ethics, edited by Jonathan Barnes and Anthony Kenny. Princeton University Press, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.23943/princeton/9780691158464.003.0002.
Full text"Magna Moralia." In Aristotle's Ethics, edited by Jonathan Barnes and Anthony Kenny. Princeton University Press, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.23943/princeton/9780691158464.003.0004.
Full textLamberti, Edward. "The Ethical and the Juridical in Reversal of Fortune and Terror’s Advocate." In Performing Ethics Through Film Style, 105–28. Edinburgh University Press, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/edinburgh/9781474444002.003.0008.
Full text