Dissertations / Theses on the topic 'History of metaphysics'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the top 50 dissertations / theses for your research on the topic 'History of metaphysics.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Browse dissertations / theses on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.
Issaoui, Mansouri Bilal. "Wittgenstein on Magic, Metaphysics, and the History of Philosophy." Thesis, Université d'Ottawa / University of Ottawa, 2015. http://hdl.handle.net/10393/32228.
Full textFolk, Holly. "Vertebral vitalism American metaphysics and the birth of chiropractic /." [Bloomington, Ind.] : Indiana University, 2006. http://gateway.proquest.com/openurl?url_ver=Z39.88-2004&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:dissertation&res_dat=xri:pqdiss&rft_dat=xri:pqdiss:3223040.
Full text"Title from dissertation home page (viewed June 26, 2007)." Source: Dissertation Abstracts International, Volume: 67-06, Section: A, page: 2291. Adviser: Stephen J. Stein.
Sheffler, Daniel T. "The Metaphysics of Personhood in Plato's Dialogues." UKnowledge, 2017. http://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/16.
Full textMcNulty, Christopher. "Pretemporal origination| A process approach to understanding the unification of the history of science and the science of history." Thesis, California Institute of Integral Studies, 2014. http://pqdtopen.proquest.com/#viewpdf?dispub=1550254.
Full textPhilosopher of science Wilfrid Sellars argues that there are two mutually exclusive images of human-in-the-world that philosophy ought to unify: the "manifest image" of common, shared experience and the "scientific image" of imperceptible objects. Process philosophy, as a metaphysical framework, is in a unique position to allow both images to sit together in dynamic tension, rather than allowing one image to collapse into the other. Not only do I maintain that process philosophy is logically robust, but I also argue that there are several instances of empirical verification of process as an ontology.
Taking a process ontology seriously, however, requires that we re-articulate an understanding of the two grand narratives that are utilized to explain our origins: the socio-cultural evolution of consciousness and the objective evolution of the universe. I call these the history of science and the science of history, respectively. In Western academia, the science of history is usually given ontological priority; but within a process metaphysic, neither can be said to be explanatorily primary. That which holds these two narratives together, and that which produces spacetime itself, I refer to as "pretemporal origination." The mode through which this process elicits evolution is through creative-discovery, wherein creation and discovery are not two separate modes of mind-universe interaction, but unified on a continuum of constraints.
Smith, D. S. "Politics and metaphysics : some developments in the history of Nietzsche-reception in France 1872-1972." Thesis, University of Oxford, 1992. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.332878.
Full textWilliams, Scott Matthew. "Henry of Ghent on the Trinity : metaphysics and philosophical psychology." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2011. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.669961.
Full textSteele, Jeffrey W. "John Duns Scotus’s Metaphysics of Goodness: Adventures in 13th-Century Metaethics." Scholar Commons, 2015. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/6029.
Full textLegacy, Jessica Lee. "Bodies in the almanac : metaphysical principles in the medieval medical folded almanac." Thesis, University of Edinburgh, 2018. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/31439.
Full textBerner, Ashley Rogers. "Metaphysics in educational theory : educational philosophy and teacher training in England (1839-1944)." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2007. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:f604b518-5ea3-4e29-98b9-cecbe3c78843.
Full textDrage, Matthew Nicholas. "'Universal Dharma' : authority, experience and metaphysics in the transmission of mindfulness-based stress reduction." Thesis, University of Cambridge, 2018. https://www.repository.cam.ac.uk/handle/1810/277712.
Full textWiitala, Michael Oliver. "Truth and Falsehood in Plato's Sophist." UKnowledge, 2014. http://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/3.
Full textDuman, Musa. "The Growing Desert: Nihilism And Metaphysics In Martin Heidegger'." Phd thesis, METU, 2009. http://etd.lib.metu.edu.tr/upload/3/12610512/index.pdf.
Full textS THOUGHT Duman, Musa Ph. D., Department of Philosophy Supervisor : Prof. Dr. Ahmet inam March 2009, 209 pages In this study, we explore Heidegger&rsquo
s understanding of nihilism as the essential dimension of metaphysics, of metaphysical experience of Being, and in the following, we address his responses to it. Heidegger takes nihilism as rooted in the metaphysical way of thinking, hence metaphysics and nihilism standing in a primordial identity. Such metaphysical way of thinking as a framework in which Being is experinced and articulated, explicitly or implicitly in all areas of Western culture, from art to science, gives us the deep history or movement of Western tradition. Heidegger considers such movement to be presenting an ever growing threat, indeed as something to be consummated in the eeriest possibility of world history, that is, total destruction of human essence as an openness for the disclosure of Being. He points out to this underlying phenomenon with various designations: forgetfullnesss of Being, abandonment of Being, darkening of the world, Gestell and devestation are some of them. In this tradition, Being, from Plato and Aristotle onwards, becomes nothing at all, that is, excluded from any thoughtful consideration, reduced to a mere abstraction. Anything nihilistic, if fully delved into, would prove to conceal at its heart an alienation to the true sense of Being. Therefore, we need to develop a way of thinking outside the dominion of metaphysics, which should not only discover No-thing as the concealment dimension of Being, thus be deeply open to our finitude, but also learn to respond thoughtfully and thankfully to the gift of Being in, through and towards which we ex-sist as human beings. Vis-a-vis the futural potentials of nihilism in this long end of Western history, the futural character of Heidegger&rsquo
s thinking, his search for a new way of thinking that would incipate the other beginning, harbours a strange Tension that is characteristic of his whole philosophy.
Simont, Juliette. "Gérard Lebrun et les Critiques de Kant: structuralisme et histoire de la philosophie." Doctoral thesis, Universite Libre de Bruxelles, 2007. http://hdl.handle.net/2013/ULB-DIPOT:oai:dipot.ulb.ac.be:2013/210697.
Full textGe, Yonghua. "The many and the one : the metaphysics of participation in connection to creatio ex nihilo in Augustine and Aquinas." Thesis, University of Cambridge, 2015. https://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.708985.
Full textSmith, Colin C. "BEING AND STRUCTURE IN PLATO’S SOPHIST." UKnowledge, 2019. https://uknowledge.uky.edu/philosophy_etds/23.
Full textPeck, Zachary. "Das Gestell and Human Autonomy: On Andrew Feenberg's Interpretation of Martin Heidegger." Digital Commons @ East Tennessee State University, 2015. https://dc.etsu.edu/honors/292.
Full textPereira, Marinê de Souza. "Entre Bergson e Espinosa: eternidade ou duração?" Universidade de São Paulo, 2011. http://www.teses.usp.br/teses/disponiveis/8/8133/tde-30092011-165030/.
Full textBy stating that his philosophy \"sees in duration the own tissue that reality is made\" in the last chapter of Creative Evolution, Bergson explains his project to build a new metaphysics. We know that the originality of his work is based in this exigency of the sense time, its transience and fluidity, as that from which reality is made. It is time to declare the temporal reality as definition of the own existence of the world and human experience without the duration one can not speak in effective causality or free choice. Thus, the requirement of a metaphysics of duration is put immediately in opposition not only to one philosophy, but the history of philosophy as a whole, whose criticism is essential to building and consolidating of the Bergson\'s thought. However, we believe that, in the philosophical tradition, there is an author with whom Bergson spoke intensely, openly or not, and that little was present in the work of scholars of his thought: Espinosa. We intend to reconstruct this dialogue from a communication space that allows to reveal their points of intersection, confrontation and meeting. Perhaps then the biggest mismatch - between a philosophy of duration, and another, of eternity-shows, after all, only apparent.
DeBord, Charles Eugene. "Two responses to a moment in the question of transcendence: a study of first boundaries in Plotinean and Kabbalistic cosmogonical metaphysics." Thesis, Texas A&M University, 2003. http://hdl.handle.net/1969.1/445.
Full textRichard, Sébastien. "Genèse historique et logique du projet d'ontologie formelle: de l'ontologie traditionnelle à la métaphysique analytique contemporaine." Doctoral thesis, Universite Libre de Bruxelles, 2011. http://hdl.handle.net/2013/ULB-DIPOT:oai:dipot.ulb.ac.be:2013/209965.
Full textDoctorat en Philosophie
info:eu-repo/semantics/nonPublished
Cruz, Ricardo Souza. "Walter Benjamin: o valor da narração e o papel do justo." Programa de Pós- Graduação em Filosofia da UFBA, 2007. http://www.repositorio.ufba.br/ri/handle/ri/10871.
Full textSubmitted by Suelen Reis (suziy.ellen@gmail.com) on 2013-04-16T19:04:37Z No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Ricardo Cruzseg.pdf: 726808 bytes, checksum: 64d77dcbfe39e391ee8140dd45dd14ad (MD5)
Approved for entry into archive by Rodrigo Meirelles(rodrigomei@ufba.br) on 2013-05-11T15:29:07Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Ricardo Cruzseg.pdf: 726808 bytes, checksum: 64d77dcbfe39e391ee8140dd45dd14ad (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2013-05-11T15:29:07Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Dissertacao Ricardo Cruzseg.pdf: 726808 bytes, checksum: 64d77dcbfe39e391ee8140dd45dd14ad (MD5) Previous issue date: 2007
O trabalho analisa alguns aspectos do pensamento metafísico do filósofo Walter Benjamin, assim como a importância da narração oral para a formação do sujeito, e o valor da alegoria em seus escritos. Para isso recorro à figura de Rabi Nakhman, um dos últimos representantes do Hassidismo. Seus relatos são originariamente orais que mais tarde foram transpostos à forma escrita. Estes possuem uma profundidade filosófica, mas é sua obra ficcional que influenciou um dos maiores narradores do século XX, Franz Kafka. Recorro a estas duas figuras por reconhecer em suas respectivas obras os atributos do verdadeiro narrador tão importante para o pensamento de Benjamin. Uma das principais características do movimento hassidico é ter transformado a mística judaica (Cabala) numa ética. É a experiência ética do individuo na história que no pensamento de Benjamin se transforma em responsabilidade histórica, responsabilidade essa que converge num messianismo muito particular. É a expectativa messiânica que se transforma na figura do Anjo da História. Os textos selecionados como base para a pesquisa são O Narrador, Experiência e pobreza, Franz Kafka: A propósito do décimo aniversario de sua morte, Sobre a linguagem em geral, sobre a linguagem humana, A tarefa do tradutor, Sobre o conceito da história. A metodologia utilizada na dissertação se realiza por meio da análise hermenêutica dos textos. A pesquisa conclui que o pensamento de Benjamin tem as características de uma obra aberta, onde essa abertura possibilita ao leitor o exercício do comentário. O valor espiritual que Benjamin atribui ao comentário, na história se torna uma experiência ética de caráter libertário. A tensão dialética entre metafísica e materialismo histórico nos confunde sobre o caminho tomado por nosso pensador, mas nos leva a pensar a lucidez de sua obra.
Salvador
Altman-Newell, Lucienne. "Is Bodily Resurrection Compatible with Materialism?" Scholarship @ Claremont, 2017. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1067.
Full textPatton, William Donald. "James McCosh : the making of a reputation. A study of the life and work of the Rev. Dr. James McCosh in Ireland, from his appointment as a Professor of Logic and Metaphysics in Queen's College Belfast 1851, to his appointment as President of Princeton Col." Thesis, Queen's University Belfast, 1993. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.359120.
Full textSendyl, Surya. "The Importance of Heidegger’s Question." Scholarship @ Claremont, 2016. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/cmc_theses/1411.
Full textGomes, Charlington Alves. "A verdade como correção e Alétheia uma reconstrução do problema da verdade em Heidegger." Universidade Federal da Paraíba, 2009. http://tede.biblioteca.ufpb.br:8080/handle/tede/5596.
Full textCoordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior - CAPES
The present dissertation intends to favor a significant contribution to the clear comprehension of the matter of truth from Heidegger, in such a way it surpasses the problematic raised by his thought, having, however, as principle focus, a reconstruction or re-reading of Heidegger investigations before the tradition, History of Philosophy, and show the metaphysical insufficiency concerning the comprehension of the truth of the being. We started from an investigation of ancient Ontology, which has as principal figure, Platoon, which according to Heidegger, is responsible for the original curve of truth: platonic conception of truth as correction, ratified by Aristóteles with the agreement concept; perpetuated concepts throughout the History of Philosophy as Metaphysics. Nevertheless, Heidegger does not treat metaphysics in a negative way, but as a place where all the problems, while question for Philosophy, get together, that is why in Heidegger existing analytics, it is necessary to step back towards appropriate comprehension, with no curves, no forgetting, that is, in such a way the thought surpasses and corrects the lack caused by metaphysics, that is why it is necessary to recover the truth as Alethéia = uncovering. In accordance with truth as correction, Heidegger ontology for truth lies in the existing ontological possibility of Dasein. Heidegger wants the truth of origin: Let-it-be, uncovering, non-concealing, Alethéia. Of origin because the word Alethéia lies in the origin of the Greek thought, of philosophy, of Heraclitus . The dissertation still brings the problem of truth in modern science and language. All the questions raised in the dissertation are upon the chive of Heidegger thought, that is why in the second part of the dissertation we treat the question of truth leaning on the existing phenomenon condition of the analytics of Heidegger: In a construction of a new ontology, this being of ontological hermeneutic nature, of the world, of men, of the truth.
A presente dissertação pretende favorecer uma significativa contribuição para o esclarecimento da questão da verdade em Heidegger, de modo que perpasse a problemática levantada pelo seu pensamento, tendo, portanto, como principal foco uma reconstrução das investigações heideggerianas perante a História da Filosofia. Mostrar a insuficiência metafísica frente o esclarecimento da verdade do ser. Partimos de uma investigação da Ontologia Antiga, nesta, tem-se como principal figura, Platão, responsável, segundo Heidegger, pelo o desvio original da verdade: concepção platônica da verdade como correção, ratificado por Aristóteles com o conceito de concordância ; conceitos perpetuados ao longo da História da Filosofia como Metafísica. Todavia, Heidegger não trata a metafísica de forma negativa, mas antes como lugar onde se encontram todos os problemas enquanto questão para a Filosofia, por isso que, na analítica existencial heideggeriana, faz-se necessário dar um passo atrás em direção a uma compreensão apropriada, sem desvios, sem esquecimentos, ou seja, de modo que o pensamento supere e corrija a falta cometida pela metafísica, por isso é necessário resgatar a verdade como Alétheia, desencobrimento. Em detrimento à verdade como correção, a ontologia de Heidegger para a verdade encontra-se na possibilidade ontológica existencial do Dasein. Heidegger quer a verdade originária: deixar-ser, desencobrimento, desocultamento, Alétheia. Originária porque a palavra Alétheia está na origem do pensamento grego, da filosofia, de Heráclito . A dissertação traz ainda o problema da verdade nas ciências modernas e na linguagem. Todas as questões levantadas na dissertação estão sobre o crivo do pensamento heideggeriano, por isso que na segunda parte da dissertação tratamos da questão da verdade amparando-se na condição fenomenológica existencial da analítica de Heidegger: numa construção de uma nova ontologia; essa de cunho ontológico da existência, do mundo, do homem, da verdade.
Jonsson, Kjell. "Vid vetandets gräns : om skiljelinjen mellan naturvetenskap och metafysik i svensk kulturdebatt 1870-1920." Doctoral thesis, Umeå universitet, Humanistiska fakulteten, 1987. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:umu:diva-61928.
Full textdigitalisering@umu
Keynes, Laura. "William Hazlitt : an aesthetics of embodiment." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2010. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.669977.
Full textAmaral, Antônio Henrique Paz do. "A questão da história em Martin Heidegger." Universidade Federal de Goiás, 2018. http://repositorio.bc.ufg.br/tede/handle/tede/8891.
Full textRejected by Luciana Ferreira (lucgeral@gmail.com), reason: Olhe as palavras chaves on 2018-09-19T12:36:39Z (GMT)
Submitted by Liliane Ferreira (ljuvencia30@gmail.com) on 2018-09-19T13:13:56Z No. of bitstreams: 2 license_rdf: 0 bytes, checksum: d41d8cd98f00b204e9800998ecf8427e (MD5) Dissertação - Antônio Henrique Paz do Amaral - 2018.pdf: 1077489 bytes, checksum: 0387588d425738ba53ea8d493aa80499 (MD5)
Approved for entry into archive by Luciana Ferreira (lucgeral@gmail.com) on 2018-09-20T11:18:37Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 2 license_rdf: 0 bytes, checksum: d41d8cd98f00b204e9800998ecf8427e (MD5) Dissertação - Antônio Henrique Paz do Amaral - 2018.pdf: 1077489 bytes, checksum: 0387588d425738ba53ea8d493aa80499 (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2018-09-20T11:18:37Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 2 license_rdf: 0 bytes, checksum: d41d8cd98f00b204e9800998ecf8427e (MD5) Dissertação - Antônio Henrique Paz do Amaral - 2018.pdf: 1077489 bytes, checksum: 0387588d425738ba53ea8d493aa80499 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2018-08-17
Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior - CAPES
Martin Heidegger did not make a philosophy of history on the side of a philosophy of language, man or being. Nevertheless, the thematic of history was very relevant to his thought, which has always aspired to a unifying totality around the question of the meaning of being. What is the condition of possibility of history? What makes us historical beings? This question is the one that Heidegger calls in Being and Time, the question of the historicity of history. The starting point to think this question is found on the distinctive openness of Dasein to its proper temporality, articulated in three fundamental Ekstasis which unify themselves in the existential of care – in sequence of originality: advenient-future, essential-past and the instant-present. Assuming resolute in its Being-towards-death, the Dasein gives openness to the retrieval of past, as a repetition of utmost and most original possibilities buried by tradition. Another starting point is the questioning of history from the question of the meaning of nihilism and the death of God, which involve our epoch, through a attentive dialogue with Nietzsche’s work. So Heidegger understands our historicity since a essential remission to what that, in its late thinking phase, he calls “history of Being”.
Martin Heidegger não fez uma filosofia da história à parte de uma filosofia da linguagem, da homem, ou do ser. Não obstante, a temática da história foi de suma relevância a seu pensamento, que sempre aspirou uma totalidade unificante em torno da questão do sentido do Ser. Qual é a condição de possibilidade da história? O que faz de nós seres históricos? Esta pergunta é a que Heidegger chama, em Ser e Tempo, de a questão da historicidade da história. O ponto de partida para se pensar esta questão encontra-se na abertura distintiva do Dasein para a sua temporalidade própria, articulada em três ekstases fundamentais que se unificam no existencial do cuidado – em ordem de originariedade: o futuro-adveniente, o passado-essencial e o presente-instante. Pondo-se resoluto em seu ser-para-a-morte, o Dasein dá abertura para a retroveniência do passado, enquanto repetição das possibilidades derradeiras e mais originárias soterradas pela tradição. Outro ponto de partida, é o questionamento da história a partir da pergunta pelo sentido do niilismo e da morte de Deus, que envolvem nossa época, através de um diálogo atento com a obra de Nietzsche. Assim, Heidegger compreende a nossa historicidade desde uma remissão essencial àquilo que, em sua fase tardia de pensamento, ele nomeia de a “história do Ser”
Pinheiro, Victor Sales. "Idea e alethea: a confrontação de Heidegger com Platão." Universidade do Estado do Rio de Janeiro, 2013. http://www.bdtd.uerj.br/tde_busca/arquivo.php?codArquivo=6599.
Full textO objetivo desta tese é analisar a confrontação de Heidegger com Platão, no que concerne às duas palavras fundamentais da metafísica platônica, idea e aletheia. O primeiro capítulo estuda o horizonte hermenêutico em que ocorre essa confrontação, no contexto da segunda fase da obra de Heidegger, após a viragem (Kehre) do seu pensamento: uma meditação histórico-ontológica capaz de saltar para o impensado do outro início, ao destruir a história da ontologia baseada na metafísica da idea, que constitui o primeiro início. O segundo capítulo concentra-se no conceito de idea, nos seus múltiplos aspectos: metafísico, ontológico, teoló-gico, eidético, ótico, apriorístico e dualista. A noção de ideia implica uma transição epocal no sentido filosófico da verdade, considerada não mais como aletheia, mas como correspondên-cia do pensamento à ideia, à entidade dos entes. Esse é o objeto do terceiro capítulo, que rela-ciona o acontecimento apropriativo do ser (Ereignis) à verdade histórico-ontológica da physis e à verdade metafísica da ideia.
The goal of this thesis is to analyze Heideggers confrontation with Plato, regarding the two fundamental words of platonic metaphysics, idea and aletheia. The first chapter studies the hermeneutical horizon in which occurs this confrontation, in the context of the second phase of Heideggers work, after the turn (Kehre) of his thought: a historical-ontological meditation able to leap to the unthought of the other beginning, by destroying the history of ontology based on the metaphysics of the idea, that constitutes the first beginning. The second chapter deals with the concept of idea, in its multiples aspects: metaphysical, ontological, theological, eidetic, optic and dualistic. The notion of idea imply a historical transition in the philosophical meaning of truth, considered no more as aletheia, but as correspondence of thought with the idea, the entity of beings. This is the object of the third chapter, which relates the event of appropriation of being (Ereignis) with the historical-ontological truth of physis and with the metaphysical truth of idea.
Gaston, Thomas Edmund. "Why three? : an exploration of the origins of the doctrine of the Trinity with reference to Platonism and Gnosticism." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2014. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:962e735e-6c6a-437a-a57b-8a00160f9bd7.
Full textArlig, Andrew W. "A study in early medieval mereology Boethius, Abelard, and pseudo-Joscelin /." Connect to this title online, 2005. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc%5Fnum=osu1110209537.
Full textTitle from first page of PDF file. Document formatted into pages; contains xiii, 338 p. Includes bibliographical references (p. 316-338). Available online via OhioLINK's ETD Center.
Carle, Gordon A. "Alexandria in the Shadow of the Hill Cumorah: A Comparative Historical Theology of the Early Christian and Mormon Doctrines of God." Scholarship @ Claremont, 2015. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/cgu_etd/95.
Full textCalhoun, Robert D. "Dynamism, Creativeness, and Evolutionary Progress in the work of Alexander Archipenko." The Ohio State University, 2016. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=osu1460755467.
Full textBarbour, Susan Jean. "Elegaic materialism : the poetry and art of Susan Howe." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2014. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:4a0decd4-dec1-4f23-9457-d4d8b58c97c1.
Full textDjian, Aurelien. "L'horizon comme problème. Contribution à une histoire plurielle de la phénoménologie." Thesis, Lille 3, 2017. http://www.theses.fr/2017LIL30042/document.
Full textMy work aims at proposing a cartography of the phenomenological uses of the concept of horizon in the 20th century, as well as justifying the idea of a plural history of phenomenology itself. In fact, both issues are intimately related for the main goal is to show the existence of (at least) two alternative versions of phenomenology in the 20th, defined by two radically different conceptual and problematic frames determining two different way of using the term « horizon », and two different histories of this notion. Thus, each version — Heidegger-inspired hermeneutical phenomenology, including Heidegger himself at his « first » and « second » stage, Gadamer, Levinas, Henry, Marion vs. Husserlian phenomenology — is based on a very distinctive conception of what a « phenomenon » is — what is structurally concealed, unconstituted, and founds what structurally shows up, reason why it has to be made hermeneutically manifest (Leben an und für sich, Sein des Seiendes, Sein als Lichtung, life, the Other, giveness) vs. any possible meaningful object constituted as a unity in a multiplicity of any possible consciousness, constitutive correlation whose character of possibility must be grasped as that of an eidetic structure the phenomenologist has to describe — which define the kind of problems and uses of the « horizon » that will be at stake: as for hermeneutical phenomenology, it all starts with Heidegger’s explicitation of the horizon of Leben an und für sich and being and ends up with the further rejection of such a concept, considered as connected to modern metaphysics of subjectivity, by the second Heidegger, Levinas, Henry and Marion, through Gadamer’s attempt to combine the use of the term of « horizon » and a renewed critic of metaphysics; on the other hand, as for Husserl’s phenomenology, the horizon is first considered in Thing and Space as a temporal and intentional synthetic function in virtue of which the unity of the thing is made out of a multiplicity of external perceptions, before its synthetic function is generalized in Ideen I to the constitution of each and every transcendant and immanent objectivity. Then it is precisely such a generalization which, as it defines Husserl’s concept of « phenomenon » itself as a unity constituted in a multiplicity synthesized through an horizon, implies theoretical developments related to phenomenology’s methodical operations — épochè, eidetic reduction and intentional analysis, phenomenological reflexion — in virtue of which such phenomena can be studied, developments we try to follow in the second part of this work. At this point, we are finally led to two main results: first, we’re from now on able to value the differentiated significance of the concept of « horizon » in both versions of phenomenology; secondly, and more importantly, by radically distinguishing those two ways of doing phenomenology, we pave the way to (and justify theoretically) a further appropriation of Husserl’s phenomenology that, more than a century after the publication of Ideen I, is still to be carried out
Jérôme, David. "La question du système dans le Zibaldone de Giacomo Leopardi." Thesis, Lyon 3, 2015. http://www.theses.fr/2015LYO30030.
Full textThe Zibaldone is Giacomo Leopardi’s (1798-1837) famous diary of thoughts. The young philologist and poet recorded, for almost fifteen years (1817-1832) and in over more than 4,500 pages, thoughts that he calls "of varied philosophy and fine literature." And, indeed, it is its variety and even the most striking variegation which characterise this monumental magasin d’écriture: the variegation of its subject matters (theory of knowledge, metaphysics, anthropology, politics, morals, aesthetics, autobiography); the variegation of its forms (aphorism, anecdote, maxim, observation, quotation, scholarly notes, essay); the variegation of its tones (sarcastic or serious, learned or familiar, polemical or poetic); the variable intensity of its writing rhythms and so forth. So the Zibaldone appears as a discontinuous and disparate stream of thought. However, Leopardi does not mean to put forward a rhapsody of isolated and fragmentary truths but a true philosophy, a genuine philosophical system. "Il mio sistema": "my system is based on a well-argued scepticism", "my system is not based on Christianism but is compatible with it", "my system does not destroy the absolute but multiplies it", etc. Leopardi’s philosophy is placed under the sign of a repeated and explicit assumption of systematicity: "there is no true philosopher without a system." For him confronting the question of the system means confronting the question of order. It is not about a simple inclination but about a methodological as well as an ontological requirement. Lacking the spirit of a system is lacking order, and it’s above all lacking the essence of reality itself, the essence of nature as a totality, a nature he cannot conceive otherwise than as a system and an order. So what is the order of the leopardian system? And to what extent does it fit in with the order of the system of nature? What is their common foundation? Answering these questions means browsing through the whole manuscript to show to what extent this moving, open and reticular totality which is the Zibaldone is the only suitable place to receive a thought placed in front of the urgency to pronounce a judgment on the modes of existence and contradiction
Pearse, Harry John. "Natural philosophy and theology in seventeenth-century England." Thesis, University of Cambridge, 2016. https://www.repository.cam.ac.uk/handle/1810/263362.
Full textBen-Ezzer, Tirza. "Naming the Virtual: Digital Subjects and The End of History through Hegel and Deleuze (and a maybe few cyborgs)." Kent State University / OhioLINK, 2021. http://rave.ohiolink.edu/etdc/view?acc_num=kent1626919557257155.
Full textGuo, Yunlong. "The structure of a metaphysical interpretation of science of history." Thesis, Cardiff University, 2018. http://orca.cf.ac.uk/115891/.
Full textPaula, Wander Andrade de 1984. "O(s) Socrates de Nietzsche : uma leitura d'O nascimento da tragedia." [s.n.], 2009. http://repositorio.unicamp.br/jspui/handle/REPOSIP/279169.
Full textDissertação (mestrado) - Universidade Estadual de Campinas, Instituto de Filosofia e Ciencias Humanas
Made available in DSpace on 2018-08-13T16:00:35Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Paula_WanderAndradede_M.pdf: 1941842 bytes, checksum: 8860b07f0e10bd95a5f9641d19a80e47 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2009
Resumo: A pesquisa pretende apresentar as diferentes facetas de Sócrates no Nascimento da Tragédia, de Friedrich Nietzsche. Analisaremos, para isso, a interpretação nietzschiana da morte da tragédia pelo efeito da ação combinada de Sócrates e Eurípides e, principalmente, quais as conseqüências geradas por essa destruição, que vão muito além do campo da arte. Examinaremos como a arte era produzida instintivamente pelo grego antigo e como ela passou a ser produzida de modo consciente a partir de Eurípides, invertendo a relação que o grego antigo mantinha com a tragédia. Reconstituiremos as análises de Nietzsche sobre a oposição entre pessimismo trágico e otimismo teórico, sobre o papel da arte como transfiguração e superação do pessimismo, bem como sobre a relação entre otimismo socrático e modernidade. Levando-se em conta que Nietzsche não trata somente da figura de um Sócrates paladino da ciência, analisaremos a possibilidade de outra faceta da interpretação nietzschiana acerca do socratismo, bem como as implicações geradas por ela na relação estabelecida por Nietzsche entre arte e ciência. Merecerá ainda atenção especial a originalidade da leitura nietzschiana da Grécia clássica, assim como sua oposição à filologia acadêmica de seu tempo.
Abstract: The research aims to show the several faces of Socrates at Friedrich Nietzsche's The Birth of Tragedy. We will analyze, for this aim, the Nietzsche's interpretation of the death of the tragedy by the effect of the combined action of Socrates and Euripides and, mainly, what are the outcomes generated for this destruction, which don't comprehend only the scope of art. We also will analyze how the art was produced instinctively by the ancient Greeks and how it passed to be produced consciously by Euripides, so as to reverse the relationship which the ancient Greeks kept with the tragedy. We will reconstitute the analyses of Nietzsche about the opposition between tragic pessimism and theoretical optimism, about the function of the art like transfiguration and overcoming of the pessimism, like that about the relationship between Socratic optimism and modernity. Considering that Nietzsche doesn't treat just of the figure of a crusader Socrates of the science, we will analyze the possibility of another facet of the Nietzsche's interpretation about the socratism, besides the implications generated from it at the relationship established by Nietzsche between art and science. We will still pay attention to the originality of the Nietzsche's analysis of the classic Greece, and his opposition to academic philology of his period.
Mestrado
Filosofia
Mestre em Filosofia
Karlén, Jessica. "Skrattets makt : En filosofisk undersökning av komiken som meningsskapande existentiell nödvändighet." Thesis, Södertörns högskola, Institutionen för kultur och lärande, 2019. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:sh:diva-40027.
Full textReuven, Genuyah S. "Commission of Two Narratives of the Psyche: Reading Poqéakh in Nella Larsen’s Quicksand and Ralph Ellison’s Invisible Man." DigitalCommons@Robert W. Woodruff Library, Atlanta University Center, 2019. http://digitalcommons.auctr.edu/cauetds/170.
Full textMcMahan, Kathleen Ann. ""Creolization" in American religious history: The metaphysical nature of Henry Steel Olcott's Buddhism." Connect to online resource, 2008. http://gateway.proquest.com/openurl?url_ver=Z39.88-2004&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:dissertation&res_dat=xri:pqdiss&rft_dat=xri:pqdiss:1460868.
Full textSpaak, Claude Vishnu. "Interprétations phénoménologiques de la Physique d'Aristote chez Heidegger et Patočka." Thesis, Paris 4, 2014. http://www.theses.fr/2014PA040171.
Full textThis thesis confronts the Heideggerian and Patočkian interpretations of the fundamental concepts of Aristotelian Physics. Both interpretations share a point in common: according to Heidegger and Patočka, Aristotle conceives movement as a fundamental ontological determination of Being. Indeed, movement (κίνησις/μεταβολή) is conceived by Aristotle as a process of unconcealment, of coming into presence of entities in the openness of manifest being. Nevertheless, Heidegger and Patočka disagree on the way that one should understand the meaning of this ontological movement at the core of nature (φύσις). This thesis is entirely dedicated to examining these differences. Our aim is to show, through Heidegger’s and Patočka’s interpretations of Aristotle, that there are two distinct and by all means opposed conceptions of the meaning and status of phenomenological ontology itself. This thesis concludes both to Heidegger’s philosophical idealism, and to Patočka’s contrary attempt to build a cosmological realism that challenges to a certain extent the identity between Being and meaning. In the working out of this thesis, a very particular focus is drawn on the concept that concentrates the entire charge of the tension, i.e. the concept of matter (ὕλη)
van, der Lugt Mara. "'Pierre, or the ambiguities' : Bayle, Jurieu and the Dictionnaire Historique et Critique." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2014. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:02bbbbda-7fa3-4c1c-af05-99842a9217e0.
Full textDraper, Michèle. "Restitution de la poésie ˸ la portée des écrits théoriques dans l'œuvre de Gerard Manley Hopkins." Thesis, Sorbonne Paris Cité, 2018. http://www.theses.fr/2018USPCA137.
Full textHopkins’ Oxford Essays and Notes as well as his prose writings are of particular relevance for the understanding of his work at large. Chapter I analyzes Hopkins’ Journals and the restitution of natural phenomena and sensations, as well as the use of inscape and instress in descriptive contexts. Chapter II analyzes Hopkins’ Heracliteanism in the poem That Nature is a Heraclitean Fire and of the Comfort of the Resurrection. Resurrection is a synonym for restitution (or apocatastasis in Greek, explaining our choice of the title). We concentrate on the dynamic description of nature in the Journals and the resonance of the Oxford Essays over the twenty years of Hopkins’ activity as a writer and poet. The third chapter is devoted to the 1868 essay « Parmenides », in which we trace the origins of the key-terms of inscape and instress as translations from the Greek of Parmenides’ Poem. Chaper IV examines the import of these notions in Hopkins’ definitions of poetry, the constitutive dialectics of poetry by analyzing the following topics in the Oxford Essays : poetry, its relation to philosophy, to Plato’s dialectics, to Aristotle’s realism and ethics, the definition of voice, imagination and fancy, as well as the analysis of the links between poetical language, truth and reality. Chapter V concentrates on the analysis of man’s singularity by confronting Hopkins’ early aesthetical theories and his more mature uses of hypostatical and eucharistic theologies, in the light of Duns Scotus’s influence. The relation of poetry, theology and anthropology leads us to examine the key notions of pitch and sake in Hopkins’ poetic definition of man. Chapter VI is devoted to the analysis of Hopkins’ rhythmical imagination and sprung rhythm, the keystone of his thought and practice, in relation to his interpretation of Wordsworthian and Coleridgean aesthetics, metaphysics, dramatic theory, poetics and the Pindaric tradition. To conclude, we focus on the importance of Hopkins, as one of the greatest representatives of poetic thought in the XIXth Century along with Coleridge and Hölderlin, hence his influence in XXth century poetry and poetics
Leetch, Amanda. "Weaving Meaning| Terrapsychological Inquiry and the Historic Industrial Placefield of Lowell Massachusetts." Thesis, Prescott College, 2018. http://pqdtopen.proquest.com/#viewpdf?dispub=10689196.
Full textPlaces are expressive, dynamic, and responsive beings voicing themselves at different scales of emergence. Placefields are the sites of research at the complex nexus of peoples, cultures, geography, experience, mythology, and place history in terrapsychology. Children are open and receptive to these expressive qualities of place, understanding these place emanations through the context provided to them by place-based educators and other adults. This four-month study at Lowell National Historical Park utilized terrapsychological inquiry to explore youth connection to the historic industrial placefield of Lowell, Massachusetts as experienced by learners and educators, reproduced through youth placefield encounters, and iterated through self, community, and as culture across scales. The arts-based research method of terrain weaving empowered this research to connect with complex pattern languages of Lowell, surfacing the symbolic repertoire of place, the somatic and psychological components of youth place encounter, the deep patterns of place that rise through the researcher, and the expansive states of consciousness that are catalyzed through complex place relationships. The difficult histories placefields perform reproduce their traumatic and historic woundings in the visiting psyche. At the same time, the underlying resilience, strengths, and gifts of places with difficult histories are vital assets to be liberated. The experiential and embodied elements of field trips make them powerful intersections for troubling the ways historic narratives are constructed. This research concludes it is possible to radically redesign field trips and recontextualize histories to provide a nourishing, regenerative place encounter by adopting complex, expansive, and agential understandings of place.
Lansley, Charles Morris. "Charles Darwin's debt to the Romantics." Thesis, University of Winchester, 2016. http://repository.winchester.ac.uk/161/.
Full textLacaille, Julien. "L'empirisme spéculatif de Johannes Nicolaus Tetens." Thesis, Paris 10, 2019. http://faraway.parisnanterre.fr/login?url=http://bdr.parisnanterre.fr/theses/intranet/2019/2019PA100082/2019PA100082.pdf.
Full textOur study shall focus on the emergence of Objectivity as a philosophical concern for Johannes Nicolaus Tetens (1736-1807). By the early 1760’s, aware of the failures of the Wolffian system, Tetens began reflecting on the obstacles to the progress of metaphysics, concluding that the core difficulties stem from the lack of an appropriate methodology. A reform of ontology seemed necessary; however, upon reading Lambert’s Anslage zur Architectonic, Tetens became convinced that the main difficulty resulted from the intellect’s uncertainty concerning the reality of its fundamental metaphysical concepts, and not from the lack of intelligibility of fundamental concepts, or to the lack of rigor when applying the Euclidian method. The enquiry into the foundations of metaphysics lead Tetens, in 1775, to undertake the project of a transcendent philosophy; one based on the insights that metaphysics must be grounded in experience, and reason must be guided, when speculating about transcendent principles. These ontological principles which come from the “theory of reason” must, however, be objectified. Reforming ontology seemed to him necessary. The task of the « physics of human understanding », propaedeutic to ontology, is to examine the modes of action and the laws through which knowledge is derived from sensations. The crux of the issue is: how can a truth be objective if all our representations are subjective? The solution is given by Tetens in “Philosophical Essays on Human Nature and its Development” (1777). There he suggests a theory of objectivity based on a priori principles of reason. Indeed, although we only know the appearance of things, the unchanging relations between phenomena are objective; consequently, by following the path of analogy, speculative reason is able to establish metaphysical truths beyond the bounds of human experience
Die Dissertation behandelt das Aufkommen des Problems der Objektivität in der Philosophie von Johann Nikolaus Tetens (1736–1807). In Kenntnis des Scheiterns des Wolff‘schen Systems, arbeitet Tetens seit Beginn der 1760er-Jahre daran, die Hindernisse beim Fortschritt der Metaphysik zu überwinden. Für ihn sind die Schwierigkeiten in erster Linie methodologischer Natur. Eine Reform der Ontologie scheint ihm daher zunächst unumgänglich. Die Lektüre von Lamberts Anlage zur Architectonic überzeugt ihn jedoch davon, dass die zentrale Schwierigkeit weniger in der Deutlichkeit der Grundbegriffe oder in einer mangelnden Anwendung der Methode Euklids liegt, als vielmehr in der Unsicherheit, in der sich der Verstand gegenüber der Realität seiner eigenen Begriffe sieht. Die Suche nach den Grundlagen der Metaphysik bringt Tetens 1775 dazu, das Vorhaben einer „transzendenten Philosophie“ zu formulieren. Ihr zufolge soll die Metaphysik von der Erfahrung ausgehen und die Vernunft in ihren Spekulationen von transzendenten Grundsätzen geleitet werden. Diese ontologischen Prinzipien, die aus der „Vernunfttheorie“ abgeleitet sind, müssen für Tetens allerdings objektiviert werden. Die „Physik des Verstandes“, eine Propädeutik der Ontologie, hat daher die Aufgabe, die Wirkungsarten und Gesätze zu untersuchen, denen sich die Denkkraft bedient, um aus Empfindungen ihr eigene Erkenntnisse zu gewinnen. Das Problem lautet dabei wie folgt: Wie kann eine Wahrheit objektiv sein, wenn all unsere Vorstellungen subjektiv sind? Die Lösung präsentiert Tetens in den „Philosophischen Versuchen über die menschliche Natur und ihre Entwicklung“ (1777). In ihr schlägt er eine Theorie der Objektivität vor, die auf apriorischen Prinzipien der Vernunft basiert: Zwar kennen wir die Dinge nur dem Anschein nach, die unveränderlichen Verhältnisse zwischen den Phänomenen sind allerdings objektiv. Durch Analogiebildungen ist die spekulative Vernunft so in der Lage, auch die von der menschlichen Erfahrung an den weitesten entfernten metaphysischen Wahrheiten zu ergründen
Mare, Marin Lucio. "Leibniz's More Fundamental Ontology: from Overshadowed Individuals to Metaphysical Atoms." Scholar Commons, 2016. http://scholarcommons.usf.edu/etd/6311.
Full textKuchenbecker, Emily E. "Lifetime." VCU Scholars Compass, 2019. https://scholarscompass.vcu.edu/etd/5838.
Full text