Academic literature on the topic 'Métaphysique – Métaphysique'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Métaphysique – Métaphysique.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Journal articles on the topic "Métaphysique – Métaphysique"
Cantin-Brault, Antoine. "La métaphysique d’Héraclite." Articles spéciaux 71, no. 2 (March 8, 2016): 201–17. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1035558ar.
Full textCantin-Brault, Antoine. "Le Logos héraclitéen : l’obscurité de l’ambivalence entre détermination et indétermination." Articles spéciaux 68, no. 2 (January 8, 2013): 359–78. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1013426ar.
Full textSlama, Paul. "Nietzsche et la métaphysique. Sur les racines non métaphysiques des concepts de la métaphysique." Études Germaniques 291, no. 3 (2018): 357. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/eger.291.0357.
Full textKopacz, André. "Otto Von Guericke, physicien et métaphysicien." Varia 45, no. 1 (June 14, 2018): 59–72. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1048615ar.
Full textLatour, Bruno, and Carolina Marinda. "À métaphysique, métaphysique et demie." Les Temps Modernes 682, no. 1 (2015): 72. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/ltm.682.0072.
Full textConche, Marcel. "Métaphysique." L’enseignement philosophique 60e Année, no. 4 (April 1, 2010): 3–18. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/eph.604.0003.
Full textLambinet, Julien. "Métaphysique de finitude et métaphysique créaturelle." Laval théologique et philosophique 75, no. 2 (2019): 239. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1070837ar.
Full textGÉRARD, Gilbert. "Métaphysique chrétienne? Une introduction à la métaphysique." Revue Philosophique de Louvain 99, no. 3 (August 1, 2001): 470–75. http://dx.doi.org/10.2143/rpl.99.3.649.
Full textReynié, Dominique. "L'Horizon métaphysique." Hermès 10, no. 1 (1992): 203. http://dx.doi.org/10.4267/2042/15395.
Full textRaynaud, Philippe. "Forêt métaphysique." Commentaire Numéro 110, no. 2 (June 1, 2005): 510–11. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/comm.110.0510.
Full textDissertations / Theses on the topic "Métaphysique – Métaphysique"
Jo, Hyun Soo. "Durée et métaphysique : la conception bergsonienne de la métaphysique." Strasbourg 2, 2006. https://publication-theses.unistra.fr/public/theses_doctorat/2006/JO_Hyun_Soo_2006.pdf.
Full textThe principle aim of my work is to examine what is the mission that Bergson attribute to the metaphysics. According to Bergson, the positive science eliminate systematically the effets of the time from the world : its « positivity » comes from that it spatialize all that it touche. So Bergson attribue to the metaphysics the mission of restoring the time to the reality and of seeing all things sub specie durationis. « Duration » is the concept that Bergon has created for describing the radical changement that this restoration of the time to the world bring to our vision of the world. Bergson admit that the metaphysics is superior to the positive science because, according to him, it is the time that is the reel fabric of the reality and the properties of the space that are within the reach of the positive science are the manifestations superficiels of the time. So Bergson’s conception of the metaphysics comes from his conception of the relation between the time and the space. With his own conception of the time and of the space, Bergson tries to criticize Einstein’s conception of them. Is Bergson’s philosophy conciliable with the theory of the Relativity ?
Ajerar, Hassane. "Nihilisme et métaphysique." Rouen, 1989. http://www.theses.fr/1989ROUEL072.
Full textWatching the world as it appears nowdays, without anything valuable worth mentioning, a world in which the coded signs of the media have been increasingly taking over from genuine pessimistic apprehensions of the analysts of the crisis in the western world, namely Schopenhauer, Nietzsche, or else Heidegger. The nihilistic experience consists both in refusing to undertake anything an rejecting any hope whatsoever. Couldn't we possibly refute such mundane nil by finding out in it the negative attitude that, in plotin's outlook, will discupt appearences, so thrusting us toward the absolute. The former part of the thesis tries to analyse the spirit of apophasis as a means of metaphysical approach, thus clearing up the problems connected withe it, say ex nihilo creation, abstract deity er personality, to mention, but some of them. Gradually, apophasis appears as the very framework common to the three abrahamic religions, the effective link within western tradition. Yet together with that, a downward process, cataphasis, beomes a must. The latter part shows that prophets have embodied the process. The author himself rejects any form of prophesizing or programming. What he aims at is settling the conditions for a restoration of values
Paillat, Sylvie. "Métaphysique du rire." Rennes 1, 2011. http://www.theses.fr/2011REN1PH02.
Full textThis thesis analyses the connections between philosophy and laughter. It, first of all, views the rejection of laughter by Western rationality. Basically taking into account the history of Western rationality, we study why and how metaphysics, which originated in Ancient Greece, developed upon the tragic-melancholy model, excluding from its building process the inextinguishable laughter of the gods of mythology. Then, laughter, connected with ignorance, with the lowest body elements and with wickedness, is fully condemned, notably in the monasteries of medieval times in which it is regarded as the expression of the devil in man. For from subscribing to such a condemnation, this research work proposes to rehabilitate laughter in the philosophical discourse, first showing its key critical role in the reflection, thus preventing the thought from falling into dogmatism and taking itself seriously. Secondly, laughter also is the expression of the being, the awareness of its finiteness and, ultimately, is the possibility of accepting the comedy of existence and the philosophical thought, by means of supreme distance. Hence, this elaboration of the metaphysics of laughter
Schmitt, Eric-Emmanuel. "Diderot et la métaphysique." Paris 4, 1987. http://www.theses.fr/1987PA040220.
Full textBardout, Jean-Christophe. "Malebranche et la métaphysique." Paris 4, 1996. http://www.theses.fr/1996PA040237.
Full textThis work tries to describe Malebranche's conception of metaphysics. In spite of the rarity of the word "metaphysique" in the works of Malebranche, we tempt to show that metaphysics takes a great place up in his philosophy. First of all metaphysics becomes the science of idea and of its object. The vision in god seems to be a metaphysical thesis because being is understood through the representative idea "seen in good". We show that all the ways of knowing depend on a representative paradigm. The idea involves the abstraction of knowledge which characterizes metaphysics. These points allow us to underline Malebranche's ontological decisions. In the second place we try to demonstrate that Malebranche's use of metaphysics makes possible to explain the structure of his philosophy. Physics, ethics and the theory of religion depend on metaphysics
Cattin, Emmanuel. "Transformations de la métaphysique." Paris 1, 1996. http://www.theses.fr/1996PA010553.
Full textWith the transcendental philosophy, Schelling inherits the Kantian determination of metaphysics as a science or a system. His first essays work towards the foundation of transcendental idealism in its distinctive concept and task, completing the Kantian programme and replying to the ethics of Spinoza. The transcendental philosophy endeavours to reflect in tis own systematic exposition the self-exposition of the absolute. It reaches its climax with the system of transcendental idealism (1800) : the work of art represents the perfect exposition of the absolute and, for the philosophical system, its own poetical or mythological future. The exposition of my system of philosophy (1801) puts an end to the transcendental era of schelling's metaphysics and to the tension between the transcendental philosophy and the philosophy of nature
Brun, Jean-Marie. "L'exigence métaphysique de Boèce." Paris 4, 1989. http://www.theses.fr/1989PA040061.
Full textThrough what st Thomas brought to light that work is an analyze and commentary of a philosophical and theological treatise called: «liber de persona et duabus naturis ", written by Boethius, nearly in year 520 to refute Nestorius and Eutyches mistake. What is done is an essay about concepts of "nature" "substance" "subsistence" that is to define the notion of person as: "naturae rationalis individua substantia". Not knowing the dogma of "immaculate conception" Boethius sets up an original thought to define Christ’s human nature. The word to save human's being assumes human nature. He gives to it universal accidents found in the Adam’s three intelligible 's ways : before the first fault (domination of reason), after the first fault (acting death), during the utopian position where Adam would not have sinned (he had not the willing to sin). Conclusion arguments about the category of "relation" called "one of the person". It sets a parallelism between the definition of the person and Boethius' person
Lemaire, Eric. "Wittgenstein et la métaphysique." Paris 7, 2009. http://www.theses.fr/2009PA070081.
Full textThe second Wittgenstein was one of the most important thinkers in the history of analytic philosophy. He is known for his provocative conception of philosophy according to which metaphysical propositions - and more generally philosophical propositions - are nonsensical. Thus understood, the main task of philosophy is to eliminate these propositions and to show that metaphysical problems are pseudo-problems. Many commentators of the second Wittgenstein's works assume that this conception affects any form of metaphysics and that he showed the illegitimacy of any metaphysics. In the meanwhile metaphysics renewed in the analytic tradition. In such a context a question raises: Did the second Wittgenstein really undermine the legitimacy of metaphysics? Our main aim here is to show that he did not. On the contrary, the second Wittgenstein can be understood as a common sense metaphysician, that is as a philosopher who gives us tools, ideas, and a method to rethink the metaphysical enterprise. Hence, he does offer us means to defend the legitimacy of metaphysics
Fleury, Cynthia. "La métaphysique de l'imagination." Paris 4, 2000. http://www.theses.fr/2000PA040038.
Full textGuyomarc'h, Gweltaz. "Aux origines de la métaphysique : l’interprétation par Alexandre d’Aphrodise de la Métaphysique d’Aristote." Thesis, Lille 3, 2012. http://www.theses.fr/2012LIL30004.
Full textAristotle does not use the word "metaphysics". The books called "Metaphysics" clearly lack unity. The science called "metaphysics" seems to break the common epistemological rules set by Aristotle himself. From that point of view, it seems problematic to consider Aristotle as the "founding father of metaphysics". The present dissertation aims to show that the foundation of metaphysics as a science is also based on the work of the Ancient Commentators, especially Alexander of Aphrodisias (fl. 200 AD). Paradoxically, the "Exegete par excellence" makes it possible to be engaged in metaphysics without limiting metaphysics to explaining Aristotle's books. The reason is that he tries in fact to makes explicit and to enhance the unity of this work as well as to establish the unity of the corresponding science. According to him, metaphysics is both universal and the first true science. As such it constitutes the condition for any type of knowledge to be established as a science. Metaphysics is devoted to three main programs : the general study of being, the study of substance, the study of the first cause. These different programs are closed enough to be carried out within one single science. The passage from one level to another is guided by what I propose to call the Principle of Maximum Casuality. In this way, the substance is the higher being and the cause of being for all the rest ; the first cause is the higher and most thinkable substance, the cause of the order on the world, and what makes it intelligible. So the Exegete offers a strong view of the unity of metaphysics and thanks to this reappropriation Aristotle's work became the origin of a long-lasting tradition
Books on the topic "Métaphysique – Métaphysique"
More sourcesBook chapters on the topic "Métaphysique – Métaphysique"
Verley, Xavier. "Mathématique et métaphysique." In Regards croisés sur Alfred North Whitehead, edited by Benoît Bourgine, David Ongombe, and Michel Weber, 113–34. Berlin, Boston: DE GRUYTER, 2007. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/9783110322385.113.
Full textCamus, Albert. "Métaphysique chrétienne et Néoplatonisme." In Albert Camus: Philosopher and Littérateur, 93–165. New York: Palgrave Macmillan US, 1992. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-137-07393-8_8.
Full textMassie, Pascal. "Métaphysique de la pluralité première." In Achard de Saint-Victor métaphysicien, 57–82. Turnhout: Brepols Publishers, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1484/m.adarg-eb.5.118595.
Full textWarnke, Frank J. "Conclusion: la vision métaphysique du monde." In Comparative History of Literatures in European Languages, 761. Amsterdam: John Benjamins Publishing Company, 2000. http://dx.doi.org/10.1075/chlel.xiii.63war.
Full text"Métaphysique notionnelle et métaphysique réelle." In Philosophie et Culture: Actes du XVIIe congrès mondial de philosophie, 305–9. Éditions du Beffroi, 1988. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/wcp1719883401.
Full textBonnefoy, Yves. "L’imaginaire métaphysique." In Littérature et savoir(s), 11–19. Presses de l’Université Saint-Louis, 2002. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/books.pusl.20307.
Full textMontebello, Pierre. "Métaphysique située." In Choses en soi, 563–75. Presses Universitaires de France, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/puf.alloa.2018.01.0563.
Full textTiercelin, Claudine. "La connaissance métaphysique." In La connaissance métaphysique. Collège de France, 2011. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/books.cdf.449.
Full text"Physique et métaphysique." In Prémices philosophiques, 84–112. BRILL, 1987. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/9789004246522_004.
Full textCachot, Laurence. "3. Perspective métaphysique." In La femme et son image dans l’œuvre de Victor Segalen, 139–51. Presses universitaires de Franche-Comté, 1999. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/books.pufc.1147.
Full textConference papers on the topic "Métaphysique – Métaphysique"
Abrougui, Olfa. "Les métaphores de l'eau dans l'œuvre poétique de Joachim du Bellay." In XXV Coloquio AFUE. Palabras e imaginarios del agua. Valencia: Universitat Politècnica València, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.4995/xxvcoloquioafue.2016.3569.
Full textBarbieri, Luca. "« Je fais l’eau avec ma voix » : Paul Claudel et la (méta)physique de l’eau." In XXV Coloquio AFUE. Palabras e imaginarios del agua. Valencia: Universitat Politècnica València, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.4995/xxvcoloquioafue.2016.2939.
Full text