Academic literature on the topic 'Moral cartesiana'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Moral cartesiana.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Journal articles on the topic "Moral cartesiana"

1

García Rodríguez, Sergio. "La buena vida cartesiana: Descartes sobre los bienes terrenales." ENDOXA, no. 41 (June 19, 2018): 54. http://dx.doi.org/10.5944/endoxa.41.2018.17199.

Full text
Abstract:
La interpretación de la moral cartesiana ha tendido a centrarse en la noción de beatitud, consecuencia del correcto ejercicio de la virtud. En este sentido, los bienes espirituales han suprimido la función que los bienes terrenales poseen en la propuesta de Descartes. El presente artículo cuestiona esa lectura, destacando el importante papel que los bienes terrenales juegan en la consecución de una buena vida, mostrando la dimensión activa del sujeto cartesiano.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Pimenta, Alessandro Rodrigues. "O pensamento moral em Descartes: Notas sobre a inserção da reflexão moral no método e na metafísica cartesiana/The Moral Thought in Descartes: Notes about the place of moral reflection in Cartesian method and metaphysics." Pensando - Revista de Filosofia 3, no. 5 (2012): 156. http://dx.doi.org/10.26694/pensando.v3i5.472.

Full text
Abstract:
Este artigo analisa alguns aspectos da moral cartesiana. Num primeiro momento, investiga-se como a expressão moral provisória é equivocada e como a moral do Discurso é retomada na Correspondência. Num segundo momento, é interessante a compreensão da nova significação que Descartes fornece ao termo paixões. Enfim, mostra-se como a moral se insere, paulatinamente, na filosofia de Descartes.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Oliveira, Érico Andrade M. "Sobre a generosidade: uma abordagem contemporânea da ética cartesiana." Veritas (Porto Alegre) 59, no. 2 (2015): 61. http://dx.doi.org/10.15448/1984-6746.2014.2.15954.

Full text
Abstract:
O objetivo do meu artigo consiste em apresentar o conceito de generosidade como principal vetor para compreensão da moral cartesiana. Meu ponto éque esse conceito consegue, por um lado, articular diferentes paixões como humildade, amizade e amor numa mesma rede conceitual com o foco num projeto moral comum e, por outro, ele permite mostrar como Descartes articula num mesmo patamar razão e paixão para determinar a melhor forma de conduta humana. Com essa caracterização da generosidade acredito que é possível associar a ética cartesiana às preocupações da ética do cuidado, pelo menos, no sentido
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Araujo, Cícero. "Algumas reflexões sobre Descartes e Maquiavel." Trans/Form/Ação 17 (January 1994): 113–32. http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/s0101-31731994000100009.

Full text
Abstract:
Neste artigo, duas cartas de Descartes sobre Maquiavel são analisadas. Primeiro, é apresentado, com base no que o próprio filósofo sugere nas cartas, um contraste entre os dois pensadores, do qual emerge uma distinção entre moral e política em Descartes. Uma leitura da moral cartesiana é feita, em seguida, a fim de localizar as raízes desta distinção.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Solano Villareal, Diana. "La filosofía moral cartesiana y el control hacia el ser humano." Revista PRAXIS, no. 72 (January 29, 2016): 59. http://dx.doi.org/10.15359/praxis.72.4.

Full text
Abstract:
<div class="page" title="Page 2"><div class="layoutArea"><div class="column"><p><span>Este artículo presenta un análisis más profundo de la filosofía moral cartesiana en el </span><span>Discours de la méthode</span><span>, </span><span>Les passions de l’âme </span><span>y en los </span><span>Principia philosophae</span><span>, igualmente en la búsqueda de argumentos que hagan evidente alguna relación de control de unos seres humanos sobre otros, y el mecanismo mediante el cual esta hipotética
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Marques, Jordino de Assis Dos Santos. "A correspondência com a Princesa Elisabeth e a fundamentação da moral cartesiana." Discurso, no. 31 (December 9, 2000): 383–98. http://dx.doi.org/10.11606/issn.2318-8863.discurso.2000.38046.

Full text
Abstract:
Meu objetivo é tratar a correspondência entre a Princesa Elisabeth e Descartes como um dos momentos propulsores do estabelecimento da moral cartesiano. Procuro mostrar por primeiro, como os temas propostos por Elisabeth se inscrevem no cerne mesmo do caetesianismo, na medida em que uma de suas preocupações era o modo de relação entre aIma e o corpo. Em seguida, será visto como se estabelece nesta correspondência uma reflexão moral com traços estoicos, mas que não prescinde de uma técnica médica, realizando, assim, a totalidade do projeto cartesiano, que se quer comparado à sabedoria, que não d
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

García Rodríguez, Sergio. "Descartes y los frutos de la mecánica: la conquista de la buena vida terrenal." Quaderns de Filosofia 5, no. 2 (2018): 29. http://dx.doi.org/10.7203/qfia.5.2.9931.

Full text
Abstract:
Descartes and the fruits of mechanics: the conquest of the earthly good life
 
 
 Resumen: El proyecto de Descartes profesa un notable interés encaminado al dominio de la naturaleza que, en última instancia, debe conducir al sujeto a vivir la mejor vida posible. A este propósito se dirigen los distintos frutos, resultado de la ciencia cartesiana: Medicina, Moral y Mecánica. El presente artículo analiza los frutos de la mecánica a fin de determinar su papel respecto a la consecución de una buena vida. Para ello se analizará el tipo de bien de que nos provee la mecánica, así como
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Smith, Plínio Junqueira. "A dívida de Hume com Pascal." Kriterion: Revista de Filosofia 52, no. 124 (2011): 365–84. http://dx.doi.org/10.1590/s0100-512x2011000200008.

Full text
Abstract:
Embora a bibliografia secundária tenha negligenciado a importância de Pascal para Hume, argumenta-se que, em muitos assuntos e ao longo de toda a vida, Hume beneficiou-se da leitura de Pascal. O artigo se concentra mais nas questões epistemológicas e metafísicas, fazendo somente breves alusões à moral e religião. Dois são os eixos principais da apropriação humeana do pensamento de Pascal: suas reflexões sobre o ceticismo e seu anti-cartesianismo, em particular sua crítica ao cogito e à concepção cartesiana de ciência.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Esquisabel, Oscar M., and María Griselda Gaiada. "La reformulación leibniziana del argumento ontológico. De la certeza a la probabilidade." O que nos faz pensar 28, no. 44 (2019): 218. http://dx.doi.org/10.32334/oqnfp.2019n44a648.

Full text
Abstract:
Este texto aborda la reformulación leibniziana de la prueba ontológica de Dios en su versión cartesiana, así como las diversas actitudes de Leibniz frente a sus propios intentos de reformulación. Como se sabe, Leibniz objeta que Descartes no ha probado la consistencia del concepto de Dios, lo que vuelve incompleta la prueba. Es a partir del período de París que se esfuerza por mostrar la posibilidad del concepto de Dios mediante diferentes vías de argumentación. Sus intentos pasan, pues, por tres etapas. En la primera, la reformulación de la prueba gira en torno del concepto de ente perfectísi
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Pla Alfonso, Alejandro José. "MALEBRANCHE: EL PLACER DINÁMICO Y ORDENADO." SCIO: Revista de Filosofía, no. 20 (July 29, 2021): 217–48. http://dx.doi.org/10.46583/scio_2021.20.722.

Full text
Abstract:
La crítica señala a Pierre Nicole como el pensador que hizo la transición entre aquellos primeros moralistas de mediados del siglo XVII que condenaban el mundo terrenal y adoptaban una actitud negativa del ser humano, y los moralistas de la primera mitad del siglo XVIII, cuya visión moderna y mundana concebía al hombre bajo una perspectiva positiva. Este estudio pretende ubicar a Nicolas Malebranche como el otro pensador, quizá más en la sombra, quizá con un modo no tan explícito, que protagoniza dicha transición. Bajo el reinado de Luis XIV, el filósofo parisino, influenciado notablemente por
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
More sources

Dissertations / Theses on the topic "Moral cartesiana"

1

FONSECA, Cícero Laclércio Rodrigues da. "A Moral Cartesiana no Discurso do Método." Universidade Federal de Pernambuco, 2015. https://repositorio.ufpe.br/handle/123456789/17504.

Full text
Abstract:
Submitted by Fabio Sobreira Campos da Costa (fabio.sobreira@ufpe.br) on 2016-07-21T14:17:22Z No. of bitstreams: 2 license_rdf: 1232 bytes, checksum: 66e71c371cc565284e70f40736c94386 (MD5) Dissert_RodrigoLaclércio_BC.pdf: 1549443 bytes, checksum: 32be05c37a9c2114041601b9ae1e2093 (MD5)<br>Made available in DSpace on 2016-07-21T14:17:22Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 2 license_rdf: 1232 bytes, checksum: 66e71c371cc565284e70f40736c94386 (MD5) Dissert_RodrigoLaclércio_BC.pdf: 1549443 bytes, checksum: 32be05c37a9c2114041601b9ae1e2093 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2015-08-25<br>CAPEs<br>O presente trabalh
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Sales, Benes Alencar. "A moral cartesiana em As Paixões da Alma." Universidade Federal da Paraí­ba, 2010. http://tede.biblioteca.ufpb.br:8080/handle/tede/5687.

Full text
Abstract:
Made available in DSpace on 2015-05-14T12:12:01Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 arquivototal.pdf: 3464360 bytes, checksum: 737d3cdafa0204cb748e1aab1b6be0ae (MD5) Previous issue date: 2010-10-15<br>Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior<br>This thesis aims to show that there is a Descartes s moral theory, although he did not leave a particular work on the subject. The Cartesian morality is scattered in his writings, but his last book, The Passions of the Soul, is the one which concentrates most of its contents. To conduct this study, we utilized as a working tool the genetic
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Woodward, Jennifer. "CARTESIAN SKEPTICISM AS MORAL DILEMMA." UKnowledge, 2011. http://uknowledge.uky.edu/gradschool_diss/809.

Full text
Abstract:
I argue that despite the fact that there can be no strong refutation of skepticism it remains that ignoring skeptical hypotheses and relying on one’s sensory experience are both sound epistemic practices. This argument comes in the form of arguing that we are justified in ignoring skeptical hypotheses on the grounds that (1) they are merely logically possible, and (2) the merely logically possible is rarely relevant in the context of everyday life. I suggest that (2) is true on the grounds that the context of everyday life is one in which our epistemic pursuit of truth is mixed with other prag
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Briganti, Carlos Rosario. "O sonho de Descartes: o homem das paixões." Pontifícia Universidade Católica de São Paulo, 2006. https://tede2.pucsp.br/handle/handle/15527.

Full text
Abstract:
Made available in DSpace on 2016-04-28T20:39:21Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 Carlos Rosario Briganti.pdf: 579748 bytes, checksum: c095b7e55b05254a7be95100dc807d0c (MD5) Previous issue date: 2006-06-29<br>This dissertation is an audacious proposal to closely examine the personality of René Descartes which could perhaps, lead us to a theory about his mission in life which is intimately fused with his philosophy. The complexity of his psyche as revealed by his first biographer Baillet is expressed in the progression of his writings. We have chosen our course of direction from one of the highe
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Jain, Sumit. "Exploiting contacts for interactive control of animated human characters." Diss., Georgia Institute of Technology, 2011. http://hdl.handle.net/1853/44817.

Full text
Abstract:
One of the common research goals in disciplines such as computer graphics and robotics is to understand the subtleties of human motion and develop tools for recreating natural and meaningful motion. Physical simulation of virtual human characters is a promising approach since it provides a testbed for developing and testing control strategies required to execute various human behaviors. Designing generic control algorithms for simulating a wide range of human activities, which can robustly adapt to varying physical environments, has remained a primary challenge. This dissertation introduces me
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Ditu, Gabriel Cristian Computer Science &amp Engineering Faculty of Engineering UNSW. "The programming language TransLucid." 2007. http://handle.unsw.edu.au/1959.4/40701.

Full text
Abstract:
This thesis presents TransLucid, a low-level, purely declarative, intensional programming language. Built on a simple algebra and with just a small number of primitives, TransLucid programs define arbitrary dimensional infinite data structures, which are then queried to produce results. The formal foundations of TransLucid come from the work in intensional logic by Montague and Scott. The background chapters give a history of intensional logic and its predecessors in the Western world, as well as a history of intensional programming and Lucid, the first intensional programming language. The
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Books on the topic "Moral cartesiana"

1

Ayuso, J. Ma. La fortaleza del ego: Construcción y cimientos de la moral cartesiana. Universidad de Extremadura, 2003.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Philosophy and the good life: Reason and the passions in Greek, Cartesian, and psychoanalytic ethics. Cambridge University Press, 1998.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Tutino, Stefania. Conclusion. Oxford University Press, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190694098.003.0012.

Full text
Abstract:
This chapter explores the reasons why the doctrine of probabilism is no longer prominent in our intellectual and scholarly horizon. These reasons include the advent of Alphonsus Maria de’ Liguori’s equiprobabilism; the progressive loss of political, social, and cultural capital of the nineteenth-century Roman Curia; and the triumph of Cartesian epistemology in the modern secularized world. This chapter also argues for the necessity to recover the centrality of probabilism, both because probabilism and moral theology were a crucial component of the cultural, political, and religious history of
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Gilby, Emma. Descartes's Fictions. Oxford University Press, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198831891.001.0001.

Full text
Abstract:
Descartes’s Fictions traces common movements in early modern philosophy and literary method. This volume reassesses the significance of Descartes’s writing by bringing his philosophical output into contact with the literary treatises, exempla, and debates of his age. Arguing that humanist theorizing about the art of poetry represents a vital intellectual context for Descartes’s work, the volume offers readings of the controversies to which this poetic theory gives rise, with particular reference to the genre of tragicomedy, the question of verisimilitude, and the figures of Guez de Balzac and
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Hill, Christopher. Conceivability and Possibility. Edited by Herman Cappelen, Tamar Szabó Gendler, and John Hawthorne. Oxford University Press, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oxfordhb/9780199668779.013.4.

Full text
Abstract:
This article examines some philosophical questions about knowledge of modality, including how we determine whether a proposition is necessary or contingent and what procedures to use for recognizing possibility. It maintains that virtually anything is conceivable, and that conceivability is therefore incapable of providing a reliable test for possibility. Whether a conceivable state of affairs is genuinely possible depends on whether it is compatible with the class of necessary truths. But this means that we must have some independent way of recognizing necessity. The article explains that ind
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Brown, Deborah J. Animal Souls and Beast Machines. Oxford University Press, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780199375967.003.0013.

Full text
Abstract:
Descartes’ long-standing interest in animals had many motivations—to reinforce his dualism of mind and body; to demonstrate the completeness of his physics; and to resolve what he considered to be inconsistent metaphysical and theological positions on the status of animal souls. Thus, the subject of animals serves to unite the various strands of Cartesian philosophy, whilst posing some of the deepest and most persistent challenges to that philosophy. Whether or not we agree with Descartes’s notorious view that animals are mere machines lacking all thought and sensibility, it is important to re
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Book chapters on the topic "Moral cartesiana"

1

"8. A Cartesian Theory of Value." In Descartes's Moral Theory. Cornell University Press, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.7591/9781501728532-011.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Platt, Andrew R. "Clauberg." In One True Cause. Oxford University Press, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190941796.003.0005.

Full text
Abstract:
Chapter 4 uses Clauberg’s theory of the mind–body union to show how a Cartesian thinker could respond to perceived problems with Descartes’ interactionism without adopting occasionalism. Section 4.1 presents Clauberg’s theory, according to which the mind is a “moral cause” of motions in the body, and corporal motions are “procatarctic causes” of ideas in the mind. Section 4.2 shows how Clauberg reconciles this account with the causal principles that “an effect may not be more noble than its cause,” and that a cause must formally or eminently contain whatever it brings about in its effect. Section 4.3 argues that Clauberg takes moral and procatarctic causes to be types of efficient causes. This is consistent with a broad conception of efficient causation, which section 4.4 argues Clauberg came to hold by the 1660s. The position that emerges thus represents an alternative to that of Cartesian occasionalists, such as Geulincx and Malebranche.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Troscianko, E. T. "Nietzsche’s Genealogie der Moral Pro and Contra Distributed Cognition." In Distributed Cognition in Victorian Culture and Modernism. Edinburgh University Press, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/edinburgh/9781474442244.003.0012.

Full text
Abstract:
Nietzsche’s writing and thought about the mind challenge some of the same Cartesian dichotomies that the more recent frameworks of 4E and distributed cognition do. Zur Genealogie der Moral (On the Genealogy of Morals), a highpoint in Nietzsche’s project of the ‘Umwertung aller Werte’ (revaluation of all values), is a proclamation of perspectivism: there is no objective perception and nothing objectively to be perceived, only perspectives on objects. This thesis is expressed through evocations of space and movement that, the chapter argues, promote and depend on readerly cognition in which embodied and enactive imagining is central. In these same passages, however, the equivocations underlying the whole perspectivist enterprise are exposed: the supposed discovery of a new extra-textual moral reality through philosophical agility is undermined by rhetorical structures that turn out to merely simulate movement, and so ask readers’ imaginations not to be too enactive. This equivocation has important consequences for readers’ engagement with the interplay of rhetorical form and conceptual content. Cognitive analysis thus gets us to the heart of a grand paradox of Nietzschean philosophy – absolute assertion of the relativity of language – while also shedding light on current questions about action-based distributed cognition as an intellectual force.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Monroy-Nasr, Zuraya. "Cartesian Dualism and the Union of Mind and Body." In The Paideia Archive: Twentieth World Congress of Philosophy. Philosophy Documentation Center, 1998. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/wcp20-paideia199811252.

Full text
Abstract:
Cartesian dualism and the union of mind and body are often understood as conceptions that contradict each other. Diachronic interpretations maintain that Descartes was first a dualist (in the Meditations) and later on developed his stance on the union of mind and body (Passions). Some authors find here a problem without solution. Nevertheless, in the last two decades, some interpretations have been developed intending to give a positive solution to the difficult relation between Cartesian dualism and the union of mind and body. The problem that I find in most of them is that they try to show no incoherence between Descartes' dualism and his conception of the union and interaction by "weakening" or making more "flexible" the dualist doctrine. I develop a synchronic interpretation, based on textual evidence, in order to show that dualism and union appeared simultaneously in Descartes' works. Under this perspective, my claim is that Cartesian radical dualism and the union of mind and body can be coherently understood only because they belong to different domains of knowledge. Thought and matter are clear and distinct primitive notions that come from reason, whose role is laying the foundations for Cartesian metaphysics and physics, while the primitive notion of union is acquired by the senses and lacks clarity and distinction even while it serves the objective of founding Descartes' moral philosophy.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Platt, Andrew R. "Geulincx." In One True Cause. Oxford University Press, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190941796.003.0006.

Full text
Abstract:
Chapter 5 shows how Geulincx uses occasionalism to develop a virtue ethics that is consistent with both Cartesian metaphysics and Christian teaching. Section 5.1 surveys Geulincx’s main arguments for occasionalism, and argues that Geulincx did not see occasionalism as providing an explanation of mind–body interaction. Section 5.2 focuses on an underlying assumption of one of Geulincx’s arguments, namely the principle, “Quod nescis quomodo fiat, id non facis.” Section 5.2 argues that Geulincx takes this principle to be self-evident (and not justified on the basis of an underlying theory of causation, on which all agency is volitional). Section 5.3 shows how Geulincx took this principle to cohere with Cartesianism, and explains the role of occasionalism in his account of the virtue of humility. Section 5.4 concludes that Geulincx uses occasionalism to defend the compatibility of Cartesian metaphysics with Christian theology, and to supplement Cartesianism with a theory of moral virtue.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

COTTINGHAM, JOHN. "Plato’s Sun and Descartes’s Stove: Contemplation and Control in Cartesian Philosophy." In Rationalism, Platonism and God. British Academy, 2007. http://dx.doi.org/10.5871/bacad/9780197264201.003.0002.

Full text
Abstract:
This chapter examines contemplation and control in Cartesian philosophy and sets out some of the Platonic strands in Descartes’ cosmology, metaphysics and moral theory. It argues that Descartes’ philosophy is deeply imbued with ancient and medieval views of humanity’s place in the divine order, and yet is also the harbinger of a modern conception of a value-neutral and impersonal natural universe. It considers the tension between Descartes’ natural philosophy and account of physical law and suggests that these two mindsets represent a certain opposition within people’s thinking that still needs a resolution.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Craig, Tobin L. "11. THE SCIENTIFIC LIFE AS A MORAL LIFE? VIRTUE AND THE CARTESIAN SCIENTIST." In The Science of Modern Virtue. Cornell University Press, 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/9781501757914-012.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Balaguer, Mark. "Widespread Non-Factualism." In Metaphysics, Sophistry, and Illusion. Oxford University Press, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198868361.003.0009.

Full text
Abstract:
Chapter 9 briefly explains how we could go about arguing for neo-positivist views of several different metaphysical questions. The chapter focuses mostly on cases in which neo-positivists endorse non-factualist views of the central controversial subquestions—e.g., questions about Aristotelean properties, tropes, coincident objects, essential properties, non-natural moral facts, and certain kinds of facts about grounding and Lewis-Sider-style joints in reality. But the chapter also briefly addresses some cases in which neo-positivists endorse scientistic views, rather than non-factualist views, of the central controversial subquestions—e.g., questions about libertarian free will, non-Humean causation, Lewisian possible worlds, and immaterial Cartesian souls.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Hamilton, John T. "Repercussions." In Security. Princeton University Press, 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.23943/princeton/9780691157528.003.0011.

Full text
Abstract:
This chapter considers Gottfried Wilhelm Leibniz who devoted his philosophic and scientific career to harmonizing discordances and unifying disparities, calculating the otherwise incalculable and reconciling the seemingly unreconciliable. The universalizing thrust of Leibniz's thinking is of a piece both with his ecumenism and with his moral and political views. The Cartesian who rejects phenomena as false simply because they can be doubted lacks the courage to face conflicts that may arise within any aspect of human experience. Instead, Leibniz refused to be daunted by uncertainty. In this regard, he should be numbered among those seventeenth-century theoreticians of probability like Pierre de Fermat, Blaise Pascal, and Jakob Bernoulli, who strove to develop models of rational judgment and action in the face of grave uncertainty.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Brown, Deborah J., and Calvin G. Normore. "Bodies." In Descartes and the Ontology of Everyday Life. Oxford University Press, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780198836810.003.0003.

Full text
Abstract:
Against a growing consensus that Descartes was a closet monist committed to the idea that the divisions between bodies were either modal or phenomenal, this chapter argues that Descartes held to the doctrine of actual parts and real distinctions within a plurality of extended substances. Four arguments for the monistic reading are addressed and arguments both textual and conceptual advanced for a pluralist reading. These four arguments for monism are: the argument from the incoherence of infinitely divisible substances; the argument from the absence of substantial forms; the argument against individuation by motion; and the argument from the unreality of motion. Contrary to this trend, we argue that if the concept of body is to serve the purposes of a finite Cartesian physics, there had better be real divisions between individual bodies or extended substances. Alternative interpretations of those passages which seem to suggest otherwise are advanced.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Conference papers on the topic "Moral cartesiana"

1

Moisuc, Cristian. "Cartesian Moral Code, Principles of Errors and Limits of Reason. Descartes and Pascal." In WLC 2016 World LUMEN Congress. Logos Universality Mentality Education. Cognitive-crcs, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.15405/epsbs.2016.09.79.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Mikheev, Gennady, Dmitry Pogorelov, Oleg Dmitrochenko, and Raju Gandikota. "Flexible Multibody Approaches for Dynamical Simulation of Beam Structures in Drilling." In ASME 2014 International Design Engineering Technical Conferences and Computers and Information in Engineering Conference. American Society of Mechanical Engineers, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1115/detc2014-35113.

Full text
Abstract:
Two approaches for simulation of dynamics of complex beam structures such as drill strings are considered. In the first approach, the drill string is presented as a set of uniform beams connected via force elements. The beams can undergo arbitrary large displacements as absolutely rigid bodies but its flexible displacements due to elastic deformations are assumed to be small. Flexibility of the beams is simulated using the modal approach. Thus, each beam has at least twelve degrees of freedom: six coordinates define position and orientation of a local frame and six modes are used for modeling
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Hwang, Yunn-Lin. "Decoupling Methods in Flexible Multibody Dynamics." In ASME 1993 International Computers in Engineering Conference and Exposition. American Society of Mechanical Engineers, 1993. http://dx.doi.org/10.1115/cie1993-0012.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract The inertia projection schemes used in the existing recursive methods for the dynamic analysis of flexible multibody systems lead to dense coefficient matrices in the acceleration equations. Consequently, there is a strong dynamic coupling between the joint and modal coordinates. When the number of modal degrees of freedom increases, the size of the coefficient matrix in the acceleration equations becomes large and consequently the use of these recursive methods for solving the joint and modal accelerations becomes less efficient. This investigation discusses the problems associated w
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Xie, Bo, and Bin Yao. "Multi-Objective Optimization of Tip Tracking Control Using LMI." In ASME 2005 International Mechanical Engineering Congress and Exposition. ASMEDC, 2005. http://dx.doi.org/10.1115/imece2005-81313.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper presented multi-objective optimization of tip tracking control for non-collocated flexible beam. The desired trajectory is specified at the tip displacement of the flexible structure, which undergoes translation base motion actuated by a linear motor. The system model is first formulated from modal truncation approach for the flexible structure representing a single Cartesian robot manipulator. The linear system model of the flexible structure always has structural uncertainties. Robust stability and robust performance on tip tracking can be expressed as H2/H∞ norm constraints, whic
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Franzini, Guilherme R., Celso P. Pesce, Rafael Salles, Rodolfo T. Gonçalves, André L. C. Fujarra, and Pedro Mendes. "Experimental Analysis of a Vertical and Flexible Cylinder in Water: Response to Top Motion Excitation and Parametric Resonance." In ASME 2014 33rd International Conference on Ocean, Offshore and Arctic Engineering. American Society of Mechanical Engineers, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1115/omae2014-24178.

Full text
Abstract:
Experiments with a flexible and submerged cylinder were carried out to investigate fundamental aspects of risers dynamics subjected to harmonic excitation at the top. The flexible model was designed aiming a high level of dynamic similarity with a real riser. Vertical motion, with amplitude of 1% of the unstretched length, was imposed with a device driven by a servomotor. Four values of the ratio between the exciting frequencies and the first eigenfrequency were investigated, namely ft: fN,1 = 1 : 3; 1 : 1; 2 : 1 and 3 : 1. Cartesian coordinates of 43 monitored points positioned all along the
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Kawamoto, Atsushi, Mizuho Inagaki, Takayuki Aoyama, Nobuyuki Mori, and Kimihiko Yasuda. "Vibration of Moving Flexible Bodies (Formulation of Dynamics by Using Normal Modes and a Local Observer Frame)." In ASME 1999 Design Engineering Technical Conferences. American Society of Mechanical Engineers, 1999. http://dx.doi.org/10.1115/detc99/vib-8232.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract This paper deals with the formulation that can analyze vibration noise problems practically in the flexible multibody systems. Many kinds of formulations have been proposed on the flexible multibody systems so far. They are categorized into several groups according to their purposes and coordinate systems. The floating frame of reference formulation is at present the most popular method for general purpose simulations among them. The formulation uses Cartesian coordinates for the position of a body, Euler angles or Euler parameters for the orientations, and modal coordinates for the e
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!