Academic literature on the topic 'Philosophical intuition'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Philosophical intuition.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Journal articles on the topic "Philosophical intuition"

1

Vaidya, Anand. "Intuition and Inquiry." Essays in Philosophy 13, no. 1 (2012): 285–96. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/eip201213116.

Full text
Abstract:
Recent work in philosophical methodology by experimental philosophers has brought to light a certain kind of skepticism about the role of intuitions in a priori philosophical inquiry. In this paper I turn attention away from a priori philosophical inquiry and on to the role of intuition in experimental design. I argue that even if we have reason to be skeptical about the role of intuition in a priori philosophical inquiry, we cannot remove intuition from inquiry altogether, because appeals to intuition are essential for experimental design.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Pailos, Federico Mathías. "Intuition as Philosophical Evidence." Essays in Philosophy 13, no. 1 (2012): 297–310. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/eip201213117.

Full text
Abstract:
Earlenbaugh and Molyneux’s argument against considering intuitions as evidence has an uncharitable consequence — a substantial part of philosophical practice is not justified. A possible solution to this problem is to defend that philosophy must be descriptive metaphysics. But if this statement is rejected, one can only argue (a) that experts’ intuition does constitute evidence, and (b) that philosophical practice is justified by the overall growth of philosophical knowledge it generates.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Gasparatou, Renia. "Experimental Appeals to Intuition." Crítica (México D. F. En línea) 42, no. 124 (2010): 31–50. http://dx.doi.org/10.22201/iifs.18704905e.2010.894.

Full text
Abstract:
Today, experimental philosophers challenge traditional appeals to intuition; they empirically collect folk intuitions and then use their findings to attack philosophers’ intuitions. However this movement is not uniform. Radical experimentalists criticize the use of intuitions in philosophy altogether and they have been mostly attacked. Contrariwise, moderate experimentalists imply that lay persons’ intuitions are somehow relevant to philosophical problems. Sometimes they even use folk intuitions in order to advance theoretical theses. In this paper I will try to challenge the so-called moderate experimental attempts to rely on intuition in order to promote philosophical theses.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Symons, John. "Intuition and Philosophical Methodology." Axiomathes 18, no. 1 (2007): 67–89. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s10516-007-9019-7.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Cath, Yuri. "EVIDENCE AND INTUITION." Episteme 9, no. 4 (2012): 311–28. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/epi.2012.21.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractMany philosophers accept a view – what I will call the intuition picture – according to which intuitions are crucial evidence in philosophy. Recently, Williamson (2004, 2007: ch. 1) has argued that such views are best abandoned because they lead to a psychologistic conception of philosophical evidence that encourages scepticism about the armchair judgements relied upon in philosophy. In this paper I respond to this criticism by showing how the intuition picture can be formulated in such a way that: (i) it is consistent with a wide range of views about not only philosophical evidence but also the nature of evidence in general, including Williamson's famous view that E = K; (ii) it can maintain the central claims about the nature and role of intuitions in philosophy made by proponents of the intuition picture; (iii) it does not collapse into Williamson's own deflationary view of the nature and role of intuitions in philosophy; and (iv) it does not lead to scepticism.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Textor, Mark. "Bolzano on conceptual and intuitive truth: the point and purpose of the distinction." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 43, no. 1 (2013): 13–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2013.774839.

Full text
Abstract:
Bolzano incorporated Kant's distinction between intuitions and concepts into the doctrine of propositions by distinguishing between conceptual (Begriffssätze an sich) and intuitive propositions (Anschauungssätze an sich). An intuitive proposition contains at least one objective intuition, that is, a simple idea that represents exactly one object; a conceptual proposition contains no objective intuition. After Bolzano, philosophers dispensed with the distinction between conceptual and intuitive propositions. So why did Bolzano attach philosophical importance to it? I will argue that, ultimately, the value of the distinction lies in the fact that conceptual and intuitive truths have different objective grounds: if a conceptual truth is grounded at all, its ground is a conceptual truth. The difference in grounds between conceptual and intuitive truths motivates Bolzano's criticism of Kant's view that intuition plays the fundamental role in mathematics, a conceptual science by Bolzano's lights.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Weinberger, Ota. "Intuition as a Philosophical Argument." Grazer Philosophische Studien 52 (1996): 1–7. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/gps1996/97521.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Kung, Peter. "Intuition, Imagination, and Philosophical Methodology." Australasian Journal of Philosophy 90, no. 4 (2012): 806–9. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2012.717954.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Weinberger, Ota. "INTUITION AS A PHILOSOPHICAL ARGUMENT." Grazer Philosophische studien 52, no. 1 (1996): 1–7. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/18756735-90000643.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Kuntz, J. R., and J. R. C. Kuntz. "Surveying Philosophers About Philosophical Intuition." Review of Philosophy and Psychology 2, no. 4 (2011): 643–65. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s13164-011-0047-2.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
More sources

Dissertations / Theses on the topic "Philosophical intuition"

1

McBain, James F. "Philosophical intuitions--philosophical analysis." Diss., Columbia, Mo. : University of Missouri-Columbia, 2008. http://hdl.handle.net/10355/5560.

Full text
Abstract:
Thesis (Ph. D.)--University of Missouri-Columbia, 2008.<br>The entire dissertation/thesis text is included in the research.pdf file; the official abstract appears in the short.pdf file (which also appears in the research.pdf); a non-technical general description, or public abstract, appears in the public.pdf file. Title from title screen of research.pdf file (viewed on July 28, 2009) Includes bibliographical references.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

WANG, Tinghao. "The role of intuition in philosophical practice." Digital Commons @ Lingnan University, 2016. https://commons.ln.edu.hk/philo_etd/16.

Full text
Abstract:
This dissertation examines the recent arguments against the “Centrality” thesis—the thesis that intuition plays central evidential roles in philosophical inquiry—and their implications for the negative program in experimental philosophy. Two types of objections to Centrality are discussed. First, there are some objections which turn out to only work against Centrality when it is taken as a potential form of philosophical exceptionalism. I respond by showing that negative experimental philosophy doesn’t need the assumption that philosophy is distinctive in its reliance on intuitions. Second, there are some objections which turn out to be related to some particular view concerning the nature of evidence. In response, I distinguish between several different versions of Centrality, and argue that the version of Centrality that experimentalists need remains innocuous. Though none of the arguments against Centrality works as intended, I agree with its opponents that negative experimental philosophers have mischaracterized philosophical practice in a way which has problematic consequences for at least some versions of their argument. Specifically, I contend that philosophical practice grants important evidential status to general intuitions and context-rich intuitions, but extant experimental studies have almost exclusively focused on case intuitions and context-poor intuitions. I conclude that those who work on the negative program of experimental philosophy need to more carefully examine how philosophers actually use intuition in their practice.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Haugen, Christopher Allen. "Intuitions and adequate philosophical solutions." Diss., Columbia, Mo. : University of Missouri-Columbia, 2008. http://hdl.handle.net/10355/5554.

Full text
Abstract:
Thesis (Ph. D.)--University of Missouri-Columbia, 2008.<br>The entire dissertation/thesis text is included in the research.pdf file; the official abstract appears in the short.pdf file (which also appears in the research.pdf); a non-technical general description, or public abstract, appears in the public.pdf file. Title from title screen of research.pdf file (viewed on July 27, 2009) Includes bibliographical references.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Kuntz, Joseph Robert. "Methods and approaches to theories of philosophical intuitions." Thesis, University of Edinburgh, 2012. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/6459.

Full text
Abstract:
This thesis is about the arguments and the methods that can sustain the epistemic support that comes from intuitions regarding hypothetical cases vis-à-vis theories of intuition. In the past twenty years, philosophical intuitions have received new attention, spurred by fashionable experimental philosophy that empirically tests philosophers’ intuition-engendering hypothetical cases with experimental methods. The results purportedly show that intuitions are unreliable, subject to demographic variation, and error-prone. In response, philosophers have presented various theories of philosophical intuition and explanations of how intuitions are situated in the justificatory apparatus of philosophical methodology. Three types of theories prevail in the literature, each a plausible option for the explanatory sustenance of intuitions’ epistemic efficacy. Selfevidence theories depend on the understanding of the intuited proposition. Intellectual seemings theories depend on the content of the intuited proposition. Judgment theories depend on our normal capacities for making judgments. Judgment theories divide further into disposition-to-believe theories and capacity theories. I argue that, beyond objections and unique epistemic burdens that each theory faces regarding the methodologies underpinning their conception and defense, no one theory of intuition can be reasonably accepted over the others. The centrality of intuitions’ use in philosophical methodology and in philosophers’ ways of thinking and reasoning, giving an argument that supports intuitions as conferrers of epistemic status, which does not itself appeal to intuitions, is a precarious endeavor. I consider various methods to avoid engaging question-begging premises and epistemic circularity. However, none are successful when the theory at hand is characteristically a priori and countenances only intuitions that confer epistemic status. In response to the ill-fated caricature of philosophical intuitions epistemic-statusconferrers, I present my own survey evidence concerning philosophers’ conception of intuition-use in philosophical method. Surprisingly, professional philosophers are more inclined to think that intuitions operate in the context of discovery more so than they are inclined to think that intuitions operate in the context of justification. The upshot of these survey results motivates my preferred account philosophical intuitions wherein philosophical intuitions are bifurcated into epistemic (justificatory intuitions) and epistemically-related (intuitions of discovery) roles. In the light of the objections I pose regarding the proper grounding of intuitions, revising the standard conception of philosophical intuitions requires two sorts of moves in the debate. First, one must offer a proviso for sources of justification that do not epistemically depend on intuitions for the ability to confer epistemic status. This allows one to justify a theory of intuition without appeal to intuition or epistemic regress. Second, one must give an explanation for and build on the recognition that intuitions are bifurcated into justificatory and discovery roles. The added clarity of filling out the nature of bifurcation allows for a more accurate characterisation of philosophical intuitions in the methods of philosophy. Furthermore, that intuitions operate in discovery roles offers an explanation for philosophical innovation and progress.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Huang, Yuanfan. "Conceptual tuning : a philosophical method." Thesis, Lyon, 2017. http://www.theses.fr/2017LYSEN100/document.

Full text
Abstract:
Chaque activité humaine nécessite d’avoir sa propre méthode pour obtenir un résultat concret et satisfaisant. C’est ainsi le cas pour la philosophie, une discipline qui compte 2500 d’histoire et dont la méthode est alors délimitée par les philosophes et les autres personnes. Quelle est donc cette méthode philosophique? Il existe plusieurs réponses. Cette thèse va donc tenter de répondre à cette question en introduisant un projet de méthode philosophique dénommée « Conceptual Tuning » [l’accord conceptuel]. Les boxeurs ne se préoccupent généralement pas de la question conceptuelle « Qu’est-ce que la boxe? ». De même les biologistes se posent à peine la question de savoir « Qu’est-ce que la biologie ». Pour eux, ce genre de questions sont extérieures à leur discipline. Cependant pour la philosophie, la question de la nature de la philosophie est une question bien interne à cette discipline. La conscience de soi est une condition sine quo non pour « faire de la philosophie ».Puisque la philosophie possède une si longue histoire et tant de traditions diverses et variées, on présuppose donc qu’il existe de très nombreuses méthodes pour « faire de la philosophie ». Ma thèse tentera donc de contribuer à cette discussion portant sur la méthodologie philosophique en proposant une méthode que j’appellerai « Conceptual Tuning ». Cet accord conceptuel sera principalement développé à partir de la méthode « Conceptual Engineering » déjà utilisée dans la philosophie depuis, dont les défenseurs s’efforcent d’améliorer nos concepts tels que « personne », « libéral », « science ». Cette thèse présentera ainsi six versions de « Conceptual Engineering », à savoir le « Conceptual Engineering » de Cappelen, la Méthode d’Explication de Carnap, le Révisionnisme Moral de Zagzebski, la Guerre Lexique de Ludlow, la Négociation Métalinguistique de Plunkett et l’Approche d’Amélioration de Haslanger. Ces six approches estiment déjà que nos concepts pourraient être défectueux, et c’est la tâche du philosophe de les « réparer ». Alors que la plupart des approches de « Conceptual Engineering » ne font que se concentrer étroitement sur la perspective de « réparation », cette thèse soutiendra que l’accord conceptuel exige que l’attention soit plutôt portée sur une perspective « expressive ». En d’autres termes, il faudrait employer cette méthode dans un cadre général de la pratique consistant à demander et à donner des raisons. Cette thèse soutiendra également que d’autres méthodes philosophiques importantes telles que la méthode de Brandomian, la philosophie du langage ordinaire et l’analyse conceptuelle traditionnelle peuvent être bien incorporées dans le projet d’accord conceptuel. Ainsi, au lieu d’être en opposition, ces méthodes sont en fait conformes à l’accord conceptuel ces méthodes s’intègrent parfaitement à l’accord conceptuel<br>Different human practices require various methods to carry them out successfully. Philosophy, an activity with 2500 years of history, must also have its own method, which demarcates a philosopher from a lay person. This thesis embarks on a project of philosophical method—conceptual tuning. How to do philosophy belongs to the category of metaphilosophy or philosophy of philosophy. Boxers usually do not care about the conceptual question ‘What is boxing?’ and biologists barely ask ‘What is Biology?’. For them, this kind of question is a higher order question which concerns the nature of the thing in itself. It is an external question for most disciplines. But for philosophy, the question concerning the nature of philosophy is an internal question. Self-awareness is a sine qua non of doing philosophy.With such a long history and so many traditions, the method of doing philosophy must be miscellaneous. My thesis attempts to contribute to the discussion of philosophical methodology by proposing a method I shall call conceptual tuning. Conceptual tuning is grounded in the philosophical method of conceptual engineering, advocates of which endeavor to improve our concepts. According to the method of conceptual engineering, philosophical problems stem from defects in our understanding of concepts, and it is the philosopher’s task to fix them. While most conceptual engineering approaches only narrowly focus on the perspective of ‘repairing’ or ‘fixing’, conceptual tuning calls for attention to the ‘expressive’ perspective. In other words, we should put this method in the broad framework of the practice of asking for and giving reasons. In this thesis, I also attempt to explain some previous conceptual methods under the title of conceptual tuning, such as Brandomian method, ordinary language philosophy, and the traditional conceptual analyses
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Urgen, Burcu Aysen. "A Philosophical Analysis Of Computational Modeling In Cognitive Science." Master's thesis, METU, 2007. http://etd.lib.metu.edu.tr/upload/12608832/index.pdf.

Full text
Abstract:
This study analyses the methodology of computational cognitive modeling as one of the ways of conducting research in cognitive science. The aim of the study is to provide an understanding of the place of computational cognitive models in understanding human cognition. Considering the vast number of computational cognitive models which have been just given to account for some cognitive phenomenon by solely simulating some experimental study and fitting to empirical data, a practice-oriented approach is adopted in this study to understand the work of the modeler, and accordingly to discover the potential of computational cognitive models, apart from their being simulation tools. In pursuit of this aim, a framework with a practice-oriented approach from the philosophy of science literature, which is Morgan &amp<br>Morrison (1999)&rsquo<br>s account, is employed on a case study. The framework emphasizes four key elements to understand the place of models in science, which are the construction of models, the function of models, the representation they provide, and the ways we learn from models. The case study Q-Soar (Simon, Newell &amp<br>Klahr, 1991), is a model built with Soar cognitive architecture (Laird, Newell &amp<br>Rosenbloom, 1987) which is representative of a class of computational cognitive models. Discussions are included for how to make generalizations for computational cognitive models out of this class, i.e. for models that are built with other modeling paradigms.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Turkay, Kemal. "An Attempt To Define Nothingness And A Philosophical Analysis Of The Ultimate Why Question: Why Is There Something Rather Than Nothing?" Master's thesis, METU, 2012. http://etd.lib.metu.edu.tr/upload/12615094/index.pdf.

Full text
Abstract:
The main objective of this study is to make a comprehensive analysis of the question &ldquo<br>Why is there something rather than nothing?&rdquo<br>, which is one of the major questions of metaphysics, and to find a plausible answer at the end, if it is possible. To begin this analysis, a clarification of what we understand by this question is needed first. For the clarification, a definition of &lsquo<br>nothingness&rsquo<br>will be sought. Afterwards, the motivation for us to ask this question, the significance of it, and the content of it will be investigated. This investigation will help us concentrate on and discuss within the framework of causation and necessity our understanding of &ldquo<br>contingent beings&rdquo<br>and &ldquo<br>nothingness&rdquo<br>. Two main approaches sought to answer this question till now are by theists and physicists. Those approaches will be discussed and compared. And at the end of the comparative analysis of these two approaches, a metaphysical approach which will be a layer of them will be sought.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Alexander, Joshua. "Philosophical intuitions and experimental philosophy." [Bloomington, Ind.] : Indiana University, 2008. http://gateway.proquest.com/openurl?url_ver=Z39.88-2004&rft_val_fmt=info:ofi/fmt:kev:mtx:dissertation&res_dat=xri:pqdiss&rft_dat=xri:pqdiss:3330813.

Full text
Abstract:
Thesis (Ph.D.)--Indiana University, Dept. of Philosophy, 2008.<br>Title from PDF t.p. (viewed on Jul 22, 2009). Source: Dissertation Abstracts International, Volume: 69-10, Section: A, page: 3975. Adviser: Joan Weiner.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Worsham, Lucas. "Unearthing the Seeds of Oppression and Injustice within Education: Using Intuition, Care, and Virtue to Guide the Educative Process and Cultivate Morality." UNF Digital Commons, 2016. https://digitalcommons.unf.edu/etd/645.

Full text
Abstract:
The emphasis of the inquiry is on the domain of education and the relationship present between the teacher and student more specifically. Essentially, the first part of the thesis outlines how the larger social-political system impacts the domain of public education, with the predominant issues of adversity becoming manifest at the level of the relationship that exists between teacher and student. The second part of the work utilizes the problems discovered and their impact on human experience to propose a virtue/care based method for approaching the relationship with the student in a way that both aligns more closely with the movement of experience, while also functioning to assist the student in shaping their own moral character. Essentially, the method being proposed is something that is meant to assist the teacher in her attempts to communicate with the student in a more personal sort of way, thus allowing for a higher degree of understanding of the unique personality of each student, with this understanding leading the teacher to form a more flexible approach that takes into account the various personalities of the students. In so doing the teacher is working to bring the experience of the student into the educative process, which should thereby increase student performance through their feeling more involved in the education being received.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Leeflang, Arne Karl. "An intra-textual study of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics Book VI and the role of the five states of the rational soul." Diss., University of Pretoria, 2011. http://hdl.handle.net/2263/26442.

Full text
Abstract:
In Book VI of the Nicomachean Ethics Aristotle makes the assumption that there are five states of the soul through which we interact with truth. He continues Book VI with a discussion of his intended meaning of each of these states of the soul. In this study the relevant discussions on each state are extracted from the text to enable a clearer understanding of these states, as Aristotle presents them. Subsequently, the role of each state is studied in the context of the entire Nicomachean Ethics. The primary focus is directed at a clearer understanding of Aristotle’s proposed intellectual virtues, and on their respective roles in the ethical life. Simultaneously, the ethical life that Aristotle presents, and its ultimate end eudaimonia, or happiness, are approached from this perspective. Aristotle argues that reason is the distinguishing feature of humans, and that man’s excellence must include the excellent use of this capacity. This study investigates how Aristotle proposes that the rational intellect should reach its completion, and comes to the conclusion that true mastery of the intellect can only result from the cooperation of the five states of the rational soul. It becomes evident that each state of the soul has a different nature and function, and that through directed cooperation they do not compete with one another, but are mutually enhanced. However, Aristotle repeatedly emphasises the importance of extending thought into action. This makes Aristotle’s ethical theory so attractive: he manages to consolidate his theorizing with the value of experienced reality. This is his essential key to happiness, which is experienced both in perception and in action. By approaching the Nicomachean Ethics from the perspective of the five states of the rational soul, an appreciation is acquired for the fine balance by which action and reason may combine to result in man’s fulfilment of his highest potential. It is in this balance that one finds the secret to eudaimonia.<br>Dissertation (MA)--University of Pretoria, 2011.<br>Ancient Languages<br>unrestricted
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
More sources

Books on the topic "Philosophical intuition"

1

Gendler, Tamar. Intuition, imagination, and philosophical methodology. Oxford University Press, 2010.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Intuition, imagination, and philosophical methodology. Oxford University Press, 2010.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

1954-, DePaul Michael R., and Ramsey William, eds. Rethinking intuition: The psychology of intuition and its role in philosophical inquiry. Rowman & Littlefield, 1998.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Intuition in medicine: A philosophical defense of clinical reasoning. The University of Chicago Press, 2012.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Gomer, C. M. H. A modern reading of Duns Scot's intuition. C. de Ramaix, 1997.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Yves, Gaucher, and Norman Mackenzie Art Gallery, eds. The asymmetric vision: Philosophical intuition and original experience in the art of Yves Gaucher. Mackenzie Art Gallery, 1989.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Nicoli, Serena Maria. The Role of Intuitions in Philosophical Methodology. Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-56715-4.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

The intuitive observations of a lowly house painter: The social commentary, political humor, and philosophical reflections of a common man. Pens of Voltaire Press, 1997.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Held, Barbara S., and Lisa M. Osbeck. Rational Intuition: Philosophical Roots, Scientific Investigations. Cambridge University Press, 2016.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Rational Intuition: Philosophical Roots, Scientific Investigations. Cambridge University Press, 2014.

Find full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
More sources

Book chapters on the topic "Philosophical intuition"

1

Ichikawa, Jonathan Jenkins. "Virtue, Intuition, and Philosophical Methodology." In Virtuous Thoughts: The Philosophy of Ernest Sosa. Springer Netherlands, 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-5934-3_1.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Lo, Suet-kwan. "Kant’s Revolutionary Doctrine of Anschauung 1 and the Philosophical Significance of Mencius’ “Original Mind”." In Kant on Intuition. Routledge, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780429491771-20.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Imamichi, Tomonobu. "Philosophical Intuition of Religious Problems in our Age." In Volume 10: Philosophy of Religion. Springer Netherlands, 2010. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-90-481-3527-1_2.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Gobet, Fernand. "Three Views on Expertise: Philosophical Implications for Rationality, Knowledge, Intuition and Education." In Education and Expertise. John Wiley & Sons, Ltd, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781119527268.ch3.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Kwan, Tze-wan. "Philosophia in Sensu Cosmico." In Kant on Intuition. Routledge, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9780429491771-17.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Chapman, Andrew, Addison Ellis, Robert Hanna, Tyler Hildebrand, and Henry W. Pickford. "Philosophical Intuitions, Scientific Naturalism, and The Mathematico-Centric Predicament." In In Defense of Intuitions. Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/9781137347954_12.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Eklund, Matti. "Intuitions, Conceptual Engineering, and Conceptual Fixed Points." In The Palgrave Handbook of Philosophical Methods. Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/9781137344557_15.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Nicoli, Serena Maria. "Introduction to Part I." In The Role of Intuitions in Philosophical Methodology. Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-56715-4_1.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Nicoli, Serena Maria. "Thought Experiments." In The Role of Intuitions in Philosophical Methodology. Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/978-1-137-56715-4_2.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Foster, Charles. "On Hunting: Lions and Humans as Hunters." In The International Library of Environmental, Agricultural and Food Ethics. Springer International Publishing, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-63523-7_25.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractThis is an interrogation of some commonly cited intuitions about killing animals, enjoying killing animals, and enjoying eating animals. It concludes that intuitions are the only possible philosophical guide through this territory. Accordingly if intuitions cannot be trusted, moral arguments about the killing of animals and related matters are likely to be fruitless.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles

Conference papers on the topic "Philosophical intuition"

1

Montemurro, David, Kim McCaig, Richard Hoffmann, and Reena Sahney. "Capturing Best Practices for Third Party Inspections of Pipeline Construction." In 2016 11th International Pipeline Conference. American Society of Mechanical Engineers, 2016. http://dx.doi.org/10.1115/ipc2016-64116.

Full text
Abstract:
The North American pipeline industry is facing a time of significant expansion over the next decade as a result of market demand and technology advancements that have fundamentally shifted supply and demand patterns in North America. While recent commodity prices have softened, the need for pipeline infrastructure may only be somewhat delayed, still allowing industry opportunity to improve practices in a number of areas. The INGAA Foundation and the Canadian Energy Pipeline Association (CEPA) Foundation have a number of initiatives underway in this respect; in particular, there is an emphasis on improving quality in all aspects of the pipeline construction process. One of the initiatives, described in this paper, relates to the compilation of a guide and body of knowledge for inspection practices and captures best practices as they relate to third party inspection during the construction process. The outlined approach is intended to have two main philosophical underpinnings: it must complement existing practices, training and certification, and it must remain user friendly and practical to use. The main challenge in capturing best practices in this area lies in striking an appropriate balance between specific guidance regarding third party inspection and overly prescriptive, specific company practices. This is further complicated due to the broad range of topics and information required that is not always consistently documented across member companies. In light of these realities, the approach for the Practical Guide for Pipeline Construction Inspection was to align material required to perform an inspection task tightly to the sequential construction process to allow an intuitive layout for new industry entrants. Once a working group, representing both US and Canadian Operators and Services providers was established, a detailed table of contents was developed and agreed to by the group. Using this simple framework, available Member Company information was then reviewed, assessed and captured in detail for inclusion in the guide. The information took a range of forms ranging from specifications, manuals to training documents and modules. Significant collaboration, through working sessions, with Subject Matter Experts (SMEs), used to review, revise and supplement the content, as required. Overall, this approach provided a technically sound guide, addressing gaps in codified industry knowledge, while remaining relevant and accessible for most users. Upon completion, this body of knowledge will be available for member companies to use immediately, and potentially, as a basis for training, individual study, and the further refinement of existing industry certification.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!