Academic literature on the topic 'Philosophy and fallibilism'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Philosophy and fallibilism.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Journal articles on the topic "Philosophy and fallibilism"
Marushak, Adam. "Fallibilism and Consequence." Journal of Philosophy 118, no. 4 (2021): 214–26. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/jphil2021118415.
Full textBerman Shifman, Nadav. "Pragmatism and Jewish Thought: Eliezer Berkovits’s Philosophy of Halakhic Fallibility." Journal of Jewish Thought and Philosophy 27, no. 1 (March 29, 2019): 86–135. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/1477285x-12341239a.
Full textDodd, Dylan. "Against Fallibilism." Australasian Journal of Philosophy 89, no. 4 (December 2011): 665–85. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00048402.2010.510530.
Full textGava, Gabriele. "Can Transcendental Philosophy Endorse Fallibilism?" Contemporary Pragmatism 8, no. 1 (April 21, 2011): 133–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/18758185-90000187.
Full textRichmond, Sheldon. "Is Fallibilism Mistaken?" Transversal: International Journal for the Historiography of Science, no. 4 (June 10, 2018): 182. http://dx.doi.org/10.24117/2526-2270.2018.i4.16.
Full textMargolis, Joseph. "Rethinking Peirce's Fallibilism." Transactions of the Charles S. Peirce Society: A Quarterly Journal in American Philosophy 43, no. 2 (April 2007): 229–49. http://dx.doi.org/10.2979/tra.2007.43.2.229.
Full textRoorda, Jonathan. "Fallibilism, Ambivalence, and Belief." Journal of Philosophy 94, no. 3 (March 1997): 126. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2941106.
Full textBRUECKNER, ANTHONY. "Fallibilism, Underdetermination, and Skepticism." Philosophy and Phenomenological Research 71, no. 2 (September 2005): 384–91. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1933-1592.2005.tb00454.x.
Full textWEINTRAUB, RUTH. "Fallibilism and Rational Belief." British Journal for the Philosophy of Science 44, no. 2 (June 1, 1993): 251–61. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/bjps/44.2.251.
Full textNeta, Ram. "A Refutation of Cartesian Fallibilism." Noûs 45, no. 4 (January 20, 2011): 658–95. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1468-0068.2010.00778.x.
Full textDissertations / Theses on the topic "Philosophy and fallibilism"
Shand, J. A. "Consequences of fallibilism." Thesis, University of Cambridge, 1986. http://ethos.bl.uk/OrderDetails.do?uin=uk.bl.ethos.234133.
Full textMain, Robert. "Pragmatism's Promise, Naturalism's Prospects: Fallibilism and the "Frieghtage of Eternity"." Diss., Temple University Libraries, 2010. http://cdm16002.contentdm.oclc.org/cdm/ref/collection/p245801coll10/id/88081.
Full textPh.D.
This dissertation traces the development of classical American pragmatism in the work of C.S. Peirce and Josiah Royce, and its convergence with the naturalist project that currently dominates anglophone philosophy. I argue that naturalism, as it is typically construed, either neglects or underestimates the importance of a rich and nuanced model of selfhood, one that captures not only the biological, but also the cultural features of human persons; what is needed is an account that shows how culture and human selves are themselves "natural." John McDowell has recently offered a promising line of thought which pursues this intuition, but his model has faced heavy criticism and its viability remains questionable. My project, then, is an alternative account that incorporates the best of McDowell's intuitions, but which is immune to the most common objections brought against his model. I proceed by focusing on one aspect of what it means to be a human person that has enormous significance for all areas of philosophical inquiry and which has a rich, if often overlooked, philosophical history. This is the inherent finitude or ignorance which characterizes human knowledge and practice, what Peirce referred to as "fallibilism." Peirce's notion of fallibilism, which today remains his greatest legacy, tempers philosophical discussions of universal concepts such as truth and "the good" by way of considerations of scope and context, forcing such abstractions to find their place within the practical environments of actual lived existence. I offer that Peirce is perhaps a unique figure in the Western philosophical tradition with respect to the importance he gives to fallibilism and in his understanding the doctrine not only in terms of its negative consequences, but also a positive theory that generates a practical response to the sort of existential crisis introduced by the recognition of human fallibility and finitude. Ultimately, Pierce offers a naturalized model of the self which is both a semiotic artifact and communal in nature. The self is a sign that emerges within an interpretive community and which manifests itself as an individual primarily through its fallibility. As such, the self is a cultural artifact, but Peirce's metaphysics makes this a natural process continuous with those processes studied by natural sciences. As a scientist, he was committed to naturalism but not reductionism; his account, therefore, embraces the work of culture and the importance of cultural idioms which are often left out of modern naturalist projects. In this, Peirce offers a promising way to fulfill McDowell's project of "naturalizing" culture and "re-enchanting" nature, thereby eliminating the gap between "mind and the world." However, despite its importance to his philosophical system, Peirce's explicit treatment of selfhood is notably unfocused. It is therefore necessary to couple his philosophical system with that of another of the classical pragmatists who was deeply influenced by Peirce's philosophy but who extended its development into detailed discussions of selfhood and community. The figure I have in mind is Josiah Royce. Royce's philosophy hinges on two central notions, loyalty and community. Loyalty is, for Royce, the means by which individual selves are connected with communities and moral concerns. For Royce, loyalty is given first and foremost to an individual community. However his development of this concept comes to include loyalty to loyalty itself, thus making an individual's loyalty to a particular community continuous with a loyalty to a global community. Moreover, his account of community picks up on Peirce's semiotic theory of interpretation, and connects his account of the individual with Peirce's metaphysical and epistemological concerns. I read the theory of selfhood Royce develops as providing the crucial element that Peirce's philosophical system requires but does not explicitly provide. Throughout this discussion, I show how this model is a promising direction for the future course of contemporary philosophical naturalism.
Temple University--Theses
Nilsson, Jonas. "Rationality in inquiry : on the revisability of cognitive standards." Doctoral thesis, Umeå universitet, Filosofi och lingvistik, 2000. http://urn.kb.se/resolve?urn=urn:nbn:se:umu:diva-6417.
Full textdigitalisering@umu
Taylor, Anthony David. "Expressing our fallibility : a conception of public reason." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2017. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:7c4b5662-7fa8-4908-a659-5f783c1ff9ad.
Full textJung, Darryl. "The problem of the external world : a fallibilist vindication of our claim to knowledge." Thesis, McGill University, 1989. http://digitool.Library.McGill.CA:80/R/?func=dbin-jump-full&object_id=59442.
Full textIn this thesis, we will attempt to defuse this argument by calling into question the epistemological doctrine upon which it relies. This method of defusing the argument appeals to some of the reasoning to be found in the writings of J. L. Austin and, more recently, John McDowell. The following is a rough outline of how we will proceed. First, we will briefly look at the skeptical argument in question. Second, we will examine the mainstay of the epistemological doctrine, the Argument from Illusion, and argue that without the appeal to a certain view about the nature of appearance, this argument is ineffective. Third, we will adduce reasons for rejecting this view of appearance and put forward an alternative. This alternative requires us to construe knowledge in fallibilist rather than infallibilist terms. Thus, finally, we will examine the fallibilist and infallibilist conceptions of knowledge.
Wright, Thomas. "Subjectivity and Fallibility in the Instrumental and Epistemic Defenses of a "Right to Do Wrong"." Digital Archive @ GSU, 2010. http://digitalarchive.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/67.
Full textDutra, Victor Hugo de Castro. "Em face do mal: uma propedêutica do conceito de mal em Paul Ricoeur." Universidade Federal de Juiz de Fora, 2012. https://repositorio.ufjf.br/jspui/handle/ufjf/1871.
Full textApproved for entry into archive by Adriana Oliveira (adriana.oliveira@ufjf.edu.br) on 2016-07-13T15:27:41Z (GMT) No. of bitstreams: 1 victorhugodecastrodutra.pdf: 751636 bytes, checksum: 0258d6d006b1d24aee758a0c34cc4d20 (MD5)
Made available in DSpace on 2016-07-13T15:27:41Z (GMT). No. of bitstreams: 1 victorhugodecastrodutra.pdf: 751636 bytes, checksum: 0258d6d006b1d24aee758a0c34cc4d20 (MD5) Previous issue date: 2012-06-29
CAPES - Coordenação de Aperfeiçoamento de Pessoal de Nível Superior
A presente dissertação pretende explorar o conceito de mal, na obra de Paul Ricoeur (1923- 2005). Para isso avaliamos sua obra como um todo, mas com foco em três livros, pois os mesmos destacam os momentos de interpretação, do nosso autor, no que tange sua aproximação do problema do mal. São eles: THE SYMBOLISM OF EVIL, O MAL: UM DESAFIO À FILOSOFIA E À TEOLOGIA, e O SI-MESMO COMO UM OUTRO. Contudo, invertemos a ordem cronológica dos textos para uma abordagem original que prima chegar à maneira de como Paul Ricoeur propõe uma solução ao problema do mal. Desenvolvemos como o autor interpreta que a história da filosofia e a história da teologia desenvolveram o problema do mal, e a partir daí expomos como nosso autor o aborda, isto é na perspectiva de uma pessoa que sofre. Para então verificar como as raízes da interpretação e possível solução são encontradas nos mitos e símbolos do mal, e mais como o homem é falível e frágil em relação ao problema do mal. Para então, enfim, explorar sua pequena ética. Onde acreditamos ser possível concluir o combate ao mal através das instituições justas.
This present thesis will explore the concept of evil, in the work of Paul Ricoeur (1923-2005). To do this we evaluate his work as a whole, but focused on three books, as they highlight moments of interpretation, of our author, regarding their approach to the problem of evil. They are: THE SYMBOLISM OF EVIL, EVIL: A CHALLENGE TO PHILOSOPHY AND THEOLOGY, and THE ONESELF AS ANOTHER. But we inverted the chronological order of the texts to make an original approach that excels as a way to get to Paul Ricoeur proposal of a solution to the problem of evil. We have exposed how, as the author interprets the history of philosophy and history of theology, he developed the problem of evil, and from there too we have exposed how our author addresses it, that is, from the perspective of a person who suffers. To then see how the roots of the interpretation and possible solution, for the problem, are founded in myths and symbols of evil, and more, how man is fallible, and fragile in relation to the problem of evil. By then, finally, exploring his small ethics. Where we believe we can finish with the confrontation against evil through just institutions.
Dove, Ian J. "Certainty and error in mathematics: Deductivism and the claims of mathematical fallibilism." Thesis, 2004. http://hdl.handle.net/1911/18625.
Full textThomas, Jean-Philippe. "Dynamique épistémologique de la science : défense d'une gestion pragmatique des problèmes complexes." Thèse, 2019. http://hdl.handle.net/1866/23807.
Full textThis thesis proposes an analysis of the epistemological role of complex scientific problems. Starting from the epistemological holism inherited from the philosophical positions of Pierre Duhem and Willard Van Orman Quine, and from the thesis that scientific practice is always based on a recognized theoretical and conceptual field, we develop a management model that proposes that researchers adopt a pragmatic attitude to react to complex problems. We explain in this research that these problems affect the applicability of theories and concepts that form scientific knowledge. To solve them, we must initiate research that will follow the steps of a pragmatic process to progressively assess the situation and gain a better understanding. During this period, the negative consequences of the complex problem are tolerated in order to ensure the maintenance of the scientific activities that it directly targets, or not, the achievement of a solution. The thesis defended in this study is that the management of the complex problems that it proposes is concluded by the rational elaboration, framed by pragmatic decisions and a favorable conjuncture, of an ad hoc hypothesis offering a solution to the problem. If the scientific community recognizes the epistemological value of this hypothesis, it will be integrated into the theoretical and conceptual field which will have the effect of enriching scientific knowledge and giving back to science its "normal" status.
Welter, Brian. "Reconstructing truth in modern society: John Paul II and the fallibility of Nietzsche." Thesis, 2007. http://hdl.handle.net/10500/2081.
Full textSystematic Theology & Theological Ethics
D. Th. (Systematic Theology)
Books on the topic "Philosophy and fallibilism"
Fallibilism democracy and the market: The meta-theoretical foundations of Popper's political philosophy. Lanham, MD: University Press of America, 2001.
Find full textReferenz und Fallibilismus: Zu Hilary Putnams pragmatischen Kognitivismus. Berlin: de Gruyter, 2001.
Find full textDocklosigkeit, oder, Zur Metaphysik der Moderne: Wie Fundamentalisten und Philosophen auf die menschliche Fehlbarkeit reagieren. Paderborn: Mentis, 2006.
Find full textDell'Utri, Massimo. L' inganno assurdo: Linguaggio e conoscenza tra realismo e fallibilismo. Macerata: Quodlibet, 2004.
Find full textPerkinson, Henry J. Flight from fallibility: How theory triumphed over experience in the West. Westport, Conn: Praeger, 2002.
Find full textDie Grenzen des Naturalismus: Das Phänomen der Erkenntnis zwischen philosophischer Deutung und wissenschaftlicher Erklärung. Tübingen: Mohr Siebeck, 1997.
Find full textPeirce's Pragmatic Theory of Inquiry: Fallibilism And Indeterminacy (Continuum Studies in American Philosophy). Continuum International Publishing Group, 2007.
Find full textSchliesser, Eric. Philosophy of Science. Oxford University Press, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/oso/9780190690120.003.0011.
Full textRicoeur, Paul. Fallible Man: Philosophy of the Will (Ricur, Paul. Philosophie De La Volonte.). Fordham University Press, 1986.
Find full textBook chapters on the topic "Philosophy and fallibilism"
Sæther, Knut-Willy. "The Many Faces of Fallibilism: Exploring Fallibilism in Science, Philosophy, and Theology." In The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology, and Religion, 13–34. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55916-8_2.
Full textYong, Amos. "Fallibilism: A Philosophical-Pneumatological Apologetic." In The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology, and Religion, 51–66. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55916-8_4.
Full textMcDonald, Hugh. "Peirce’s Theory of Truth and Fallibilism." In Richard J. Bernstein and the Pragmatist Turn in Contemporary Philosophy, 71–77. London: Palgrave Macmillan UK, 2014. http://dx.doi.org/10.1057/9781137352705_5.
Full textLillebø, Jonas Gamborg. "Fallibilism, Problematization, and the History of Thought." In The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology, and Religion, 35–50. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55916-8_3.
Full textKim, Seung Chul. "A Pluralistic Pluralism: With Some Remarks on Fallibilism." In The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology, and Religion, 125–39. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55916-8_8.
Full textDahill, Lisa E. "“Unworthy of the Earth”: Fallibilism, Place, Terra Nullius, and Christian Mission." In The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology, and Religion, 67–88. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55916-8_5.
Full textHastings, Thomas John. "Restoring the Pro Nobis > Pro Me: A Translated Religion, Polycentric Ecumenism, and Moderate Fallibilism." In The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology, and Religion, 141–57. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55916-8_9.
Full textAnderson, Ronald. "Balancing Necessity and Fallibilism: Charles Sanders Peirce on the Status of Mathematics and its Intersection with the Inquiry into Nature." In The Western Ontario Series in Philosophy of Science, 15–42. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-1-4020-9107-0_2.
Full textBorga, Marco. "From Certainty to Fallibility in Mathematics?" In Philosophy of Mathematics Today, 39–50. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1997. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-5690-5_2.
Full textHastings, Thomas John, and Knut-Willy Sæther. "A Fallibilist Approach in the Age of COVID-19 and Climate Change." In The Grace of Being Fallible in Philosophy, Theology, and Religion, 1–11. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-55916-8_1.
Full text