Academic literature on the topic 'Philosophy of criminal law'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Philosophy of criminal law.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Journal articles on the topic "Philosophy of criminal law"
Murphy, Jeffrie G., and Douglas N. Husak. "Philosophy of Criminal Law." Noûs 26, no. 4 (December 1992): 527. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2216035.
Full textHeinrich, Stefanie. "Criminal Law and Philosophy." International Criminal Law Review 10, no. 5 (October 1, 2010): 873–74. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/157181210x528423.
Full textSnarski, Tomasz. "Why criminal law needs a philosophy of law?" Polish Journal of Criminology 4, no. 1 (October 3, 2018): 1–10. http://dx.doi.org/10.5604/01.3001.0012.5964.
Full textStaflund, Darryl. "Philosophy and the Criminal Law." Philosophers' Magazine, no. 5 (1999): 59. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/tpm19995142.
Full textJacobsen, Jørn. "Philosophy, Theory and Criminal Law." Jurisprudence 5, no. 1 (July 8, 2014): 209–16. http://dx.doi.org/10.5235/20403313.5.1.209.
Full textReiff, Mark R. "International Criminal Law and Philosophy." Social Theory and Practice 37, no. 2 (2011): 370–78. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/soctheorpract201137221.
Full textKhilyuta, Vadim Vladimirovich. "Philosophy of Globalization of Criminal Law." Russian Journal of Legal Studies 6, no. 2 (June 15, 2019): 73–81. http://dx.doi.org/10.17816/rjls18486.
Full textKatz, Leo. "Philosophy of Criminal Law. Douglas Husak." Ethics 99, no. 4 (July 1989): 953–54. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/293132.
Full textLee, Youngjae. "What is Philosophy of Criminal Law?" Criminal Law and Philosophy 8, no. 3 (March 14, 2013): 671–85. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11572-013-9222-0.
Full textZedner, Lucia. "Terrorizing Criminal Law." Criminal Law and Philosophy 8, no. 1 (June 17, 2012): 99–121. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11572-012-9166-9.
Full textDissertations / Theses on the topic "Philosophy of criminal law"
Wirts, Amelia Marie. "Criminal Oppression: A Non-Ideal Theory of Criminal Law and Punishment." Thesis, Boston College, 2020. http://hdl.handle.net/2345/bc-ir:108954.
Full textThis dissertation defines and defends the concept of ‘criminal oppression.’ Criminal oppression occurs when people are excluded from full participation in important social and political institutions because they are perceived to have violated certain community norms. Oppression is primarily a structural phenomenon, in which practices of formal and informal institutions unjustly harm people based on group membership. In structural oppression, there is rarely an individual who can be said to be responsible for the oppression, but I argue that at times, individuals may also be agents of oppression when they create, perpetuate, or exacerbate structural oppression. Applying this theory of oppression, the criminal justice system in the United States is an oppressive structure that unjustly harms those considered to be ‘criminals’ through a variety of practices. There are three categories of unjust practices: policing, adjudication and punishment, and collateral effects of arrest and conviction. These three categories of practices create the social group ‘criminals’ by subjecting certain people to these kinds of treatments. I use the word ‘criminal’ to describe those who are treated as criminals by police, the courts, and even private individuals like employers. To be a ‘criminal,’ it is not necessary that one has committed a crime or been convicted of a crime. Racial and criminal oppression deeply related historically and conceptually. Nevertheless, they are distinct kinds of oppression. In the United States, those who are not racially oppressed but are ‘criminals’ face many of the same unjust obstacles as those who are racially oppressed in addition to being ‘criminals.’ Some may argue that ‘criminals’ duly convicted of crimes deserve to be socially and politically excluded. But, I argue that the criminal justice system is not properly conceived of as an apolitical institution that can assess moral blameworthiness. Nor should it be able to offer punishments that amount to social and political exclusion. Instead, the criminal justice system is one political institution amongst many, and it ought to be governed by the same principles of liberty and equality that govern other political institutions. Criminal law’s proper function is to facilitate government as a system social cooperation. Therefore, it ought to respond to criminal acts with actions designed to promote inclusion rather than exclusion. Moreover, even if someone has committed a crime, that does not mean that they ought to be subject to violence or permanent second-class status. Finally, I address specific, feminism-driven arguments for using the criminal justice system to fight violence against women. Some feminists argue that the expressivist function of punishment—the ability of punishment to express disapproval and disavowal—makes it a perfect tool for fighting the normalization of violence against women. The problem, they contend, is that this violence is under-punished in the United States, and the solution to ending violence against women is to increase prosecutions and advocate for harsher punishments because punishment will change the social norms and make violence against women rarer. To this, I argue that those who create laws or mete out punishments do not have control over the social meaning of punishment with precision. The historical and present-day oppressive features of criminal law and punishment interfere with the ability of prosecution and punishment to condemn certain types of acts without also condemning people. Thus, feminists who try to use the criminal justice system to fight gender-based violence will find it to be ineffective and potentially harmful to the already oppressed group of ‘criminals.” Chapter 1argues that ‘criminals’ are oppressed using a structural model of oppression that focuses on how collections of institutional policies and practices can create and maintain unjust power relations between groups of people. I will also use an externalist theory of group identity to argue that being arrested or convicted of a crime is not necessary or sufficient for membership in the social group ‘criminal.’ Chapter 2 explains the relationship between racial oppression and the oppression of ‘criminals,’ noting the historical development of the modern prison system. Chapter 3 argues that the proper role of criminal law is to support systems of social cooperation, not to punish pre-political wrongs. I will suggest that criminal law is in essence part of the social contract, not a separate sphere of justice to which distinctive, retributive principles apply. Instead, the criminal law cannot determine moral blameworthiness and is only justified in sanctioning rule violations for the sake of supporting social cooperation in a society whose institutions are worth supporting. In Chapter 4, I propose a feminist, expressivist defense of the use of prosecution and harsh punishment as a response to rape and domestic violence that takes the structural nature of violence against women into account. Chapter 5, however, demonstrates why even this theory cannot justify incarceration in the non-ideal sphere because of the oppressive history and practice of the American criminal justice system
Thesis (PhD) — Boston College, 2020
Submitted to: Boston College. Graduate School of Arts and Sciences
Discipline: Philosophy
Benoliel, Barbara. "Public Humiliation as a Mitigator in Criminal Sentencing." ScholarWorks, 2006. https://scholarworks.waldenu.edu/dissertations/388.
Full textKennedy, Chloe Jane Sophia. "Criminal law and the Scottish moral tradition." Thesis, University of Edinburgh, 2014. http://hdl.handle.net/1842/17935.
Full textBlaas, Fey-Constanze. "Double criminality in international extradition law." Thesis, Stellenbosch : Stellenbosch University, 2003. http://hdl.handle.net/10019.1/53398.
Full textENGLISH ABSTRACT: The object of the thesis is to examine the content and status of the double criminality principle in international extradition law. The double criminality principle says a fugitive c annat be extradited unless the conduct for which his extradition is sought is criminal in both the requesting state and the requested state. This thesis is based on a study of sources of international law and domestic law and ideas presented in legal literature. The double criminality principle has developed over several centuries and it has been embraced by most states in one form or the other. The principle serves several purposes, of which the most dominant is the notion of state sovereignty. States apply the double criminality principle differently due to its multiple rationale. Legal literature has distinguished two main methods of interpretation, called interpretation in abstracto and in concreto. Whereas the in abstracto method focuses on the theoretical punishability of the conduct, the in concreto method attaches importance to all factual, personal and legal aspects. There are also ways of interpretation that are a combination of these two methods. Most states can be classified into one of the two main groups of interpretation, but in general most states have adopted a specific method of interpretation that is unique to each particular state. There is thus no uniform method of interpretation in international extradition law. This thesis attempts to determine whether the double criminality principle has become a rule of customary international law. Though most instruments on international or domestic extradition law include the double criminality principle, the strong disagreement among legal scholars as to the legal status of the principle leads to the conclusion that the double criminality principle is not a rule of international law today. This thesis contains an examination of whether the principle of double criminality can be classified as an international human rights norm. Though the principle of double criminality has striking similarities with human rights as it partly aims at protecting individuals facing extradition, there are also a number of aspects that distinguish the principle from traditional human rights. This is partly attributable to the fact that international extradition law is not the arena where general international human rights have developed. It is therefore concluded that the double criminality principle does not form part of international human rights law.
AFRIKAANSE OPSOMMING: Die oogmerk van hierdie tesis is om die inhoud en status van die beginsel van dubbelkriminaliteit in internasionale uitleweringsreg te ondersoek. Hierdie beginsel behels dat die handeling ten opsigte waarvan die uitlewering versoek is, misdade in beide die staat wat uitlewering versoek as die staat waarvan uitlewering versoek word, is. Die metode wat hierdie tesis onderlê is 'n literatuurstudie van bronne in die internasionale en nasionale reg. Die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel het oor etlike eeue ontwikkel. Dit word gevind in die meeste regstelsels. Die beginsel dien verskeie oogmerke, waarvan staatsoewereiniteit sekerlik die belangrikste is. State pas die beginselop verskillende maniere toe weens die verskeie bestaansredes vir die beginsel. Regsliteratuur tref 'n onderskeid tussen twee belangrike metodes van interpretasie, naamlik die in abstracto en in concreto benaderings. Terwyl die in abstracto metode op die teoretiese strafbaarheid van die handeling fokus, plaas die in concreto benadering klem op die feitelike, persoonlike en konkrete regsaspekte. Daar is kombinasies van hierdie metodes. Meeste state kan geklassifiseer word volgens die twee benaderings, maar tog pas state hierdie benaderings by hul besondere behoeftes aan. Daar is dus geen uniforme metode van interpretasie in internasionale uitleweringsreg nie. Hierdie tesis poog om te bepaal of die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel 'n reël van gemeenregtelike internasionale reg geword het. Alhoewel meeste wetgewing op die terrein van internasionale en nasionale uitleweringsreg die beginsel van dubbelkriminalitiet insluit, is daar sterk meningsverskilonder regsgeleerdes tov die status van die beinsel. Die gevolgtrekking is dat die beginsel nie 'n algemene reël van die internasionale reg is nie. Ten slotte word daar gekyk of die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel as 'n beginsel van internasionale menseregte geklassifiseer kan word. Alhoewel die beginsel ooreemste met menseregtenorme toon - veral die beskerming van die individu in uitleweringsaangeleenthede - is daar 'n aantal aspekte wat d it van menseregte 0 nderskei. I nternasionale uitleweringsreg en internasionale menseregte deel nie dieselfde ontwikkelingsgeskiedenis nie. Die gevolgtrekking is dus dat die dubbelkriminaliteitsbeginsel nie deel vorm van internasionale menseregte nie.
Edwards, James Robert. "Uses and misuses of criminalisation." Thesis, University of Oxford, 2011. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:6f8c71da-bdcf-4412-aeaf-5463544b5908.
Full textLuth, Margreet J. "Emotions in court : should the criminal justice process be concerned with the offender's inner feelings?" Thesis, University of Oxford, 2014. http://ora.ox.ac.uk/objects/uuid:0c48e482-6c50-413a-9a5e-dbdca8c7d3d0.
Full textMallory, Jeri. "Comparisons of the Soul: A Foucauldian Analysis of Reasonable Doubt." Scholarship @ Claremont, 2019. https://scholarship.claremont.edu/scripps_theses/1409.
Full textHaselkorn, Amelia A. "When Society Becomes the Criminal: An Exploration of Society’s Responsibilities to the Wrongfully Convicted." Scholarship @ Claremont, 2016. http://scholarship.claremont.edu/pitzer_theses/84.
Full textGiddens, Thomas Philip. "Comics, crime, and the moral self : an interdisciplinary study of criminal identity." Thesis, University of Exeter, 2011. http://hdl.handle.net/10036/3622.
Full textParsley, Stephen. "Rethinking Legal Retribution." Digital Archive @ GSU, 2011. http://digitalarchive.gsu.edu/philosophy_theses/98.
Full textBooks on the topic "Philosophy of criminal law"
May, Larry, and Zach Hoskins, eds. International Criminal Law and Philosophy. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/cbo9780511642265.
Full textLarry, May, and Hoskins Zachary 1973-, eds. International criminal law and philosophy. New York: Cambridge University Press, 2010.
Find full textThe philosophy of criminal law: Selected essays. New York: Oxford University Press, 2010.
Find full textViens, A. M., John Coggon, and Anthony S. Kessel, eds. Criminal Law, Philosophy and Public Health Practice. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 2013. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/cbo9781139137065.
Full textDuff, Antony. Philosophical foundations of criminal law. Oxford: Oxford University Press, 2011.
Find full textSá, Alvino Augusto de. Criminologia criminal e psicologia criminal. 2nd ed. São Paulo, SP, Brasil: Editora Revista dos Tribunais, 2010.
Find full textBook chapters on the topic "Philosophy of criminal law"
Katz, Leo. "Criminal Law." In A Companion to Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, 90–102. Oxford, UK: Wiley-Blackwell, 2010. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9781444320114.ch4.
Full textLagier, Daniel González. "The Debate in Criminal Law." In Law and Philosophy Library, 39–54. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2003. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-017-0205-8_4.
Full textHusak, Douglas. "Criminal Law Theory." In The Blackwell Guide to the Philosophy of Law and Legal Theory, 107–21. Oxford, UK: Blackwell Publishing Ltd, 2008. http://dx.doi.org/10.1002/9780470690116.ch7.
Full textLindgren, J. Ralph. "Adam Smith’s Treatment of Criminal Law." In Law and Philosophy Library, 63–81. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 1994. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-011-0748-8_4.
Full textDuff, R. A., and S. E. Marshall. "Liberty and Equality in Criminal Law." In Encyclopedia of the Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy, 1–7. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-007-6730-0_833-1.
Full textMorse, Stephen J. "Criminal Law and Addiction." In The Routledge Handbook of Philosophy and Science of Addiction, 540–53. 1 [edition]. | New York : Routledge, 2018. | Series: Routledge handbooks in philosophy: Routledge, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315689197-45.
Full textHurd, Heidi M. "Paternalism and the criminal law." In The Routledge Handbook of the Philosophy of Paternalism, 277–92. New York : Routledge, 2018. | Series: Routledge handbooks in philosophy: Routledge, 2018. http://dx.doi.org/10.4324/9781315657080-23.
Full textFlanders, Chad. "Political Philosophy and Punishment." In The Palgrave Handbook of Applied Ethics and the Criminal Law, 521–45. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-22811-8_22.
Full textRobinson, John H., and Roberta M. Berry. "Unraveling the Codes: The Dialectic Between Knowledge of the Moral Person and Knowledge of the Genetic Person in Criminal Law." In Philosophy and Medicine, 287–317. Dordrecht: Springer Netherlands, 2002. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-94-010-0269-1_14.
Full textKeiler, Johannes, Michele Panzavolta, and David Roef. "Criminal Law." In Introduction to Law, 129–63. Cham: Springer International Publishing, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/978-3-319-57252-9_7.
Full textConference papers on the topic "Philosophy of criminal law"
Bogunović, Mirjana. "Incestum: love or criminal act?" In XXVI World Congress of Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy. Initia Via, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.17931/ivr2013_sws81_02.
Full textBiancu, Stefano. "Criminal law and cultural diversity: a philosophical approach (from a European Standpoint)." In XXVI World Congress of Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy. Initia Via, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.17931/ivr2013_wg167_01.
Full textTabatchikova, Anastasiya. "Problems of Balancing Private and Public Interests of States in the Criminalisation of International Crimes." In The Public/Private in Modern Civilization, the 22nd Russian Scientific-Practical Conference (with international participation) (Yekaterinburg, April 16-17, 2020). Liberal Arts University – University for Humanities, Yekaterinburg, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.35853/ufh-public/private-2020-22.
Full textZaharia, Virginia. "The Philosophical Vision of Legal Punishment." In World Lumen Congress 2021, May 26-30, 2021, Iasi, Romania. LUMEN Publishing House, 2022. http://dx.doi.org/10.18662/wlc2021/73.
Full textHosnah, Asmak ul. "Initiating of the Principle of Harmony in Criminal Law at the Community Relating to the Culture of Punitive Action based on the Perspective of Pancasila Law Philosophy." In 2nd Asian Education Symposium. SCITEPRESS - Science and Technology Publications, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.5220/0007302802840287.
Full textAugusto Suzuki Dias Cintra, Rodrigo, and Daniel Francisco Nagao Menezes. "General Law versus Specific Law." In XXVI World Congress of Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy. Initia Via, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.17931/ivr2013_wg146_01.
Full textRomanovna, Afanasieva Olga, Afanasyev Pavel Borisovich, Goncharova Maria Vitalievna, Novikov Valery Anatolyevich, and Shiyan Valentina Ivanovna. "Criminal Community (Criminal Organization): Concept And Criminal Law Signs." In International Conference on Social and Cultural Transformations in the Context of Modern Globalism. European Publisher, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.15405/epsbs.2021.11.4.
Full textDzhindzholiya, Raul', Ruslan Zhirov, and Azamat Dzuev. "EXEMPTION FROM CRIMINAL RESPONSIBILITY AND PUNISHMENTAS A FROM OF CRIMINAL PROTECTION." In Law and law: problems of theory and practice. ru: Publishing Center RIOR, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.29039/02033-3/198-206.
Full textDumas, Martin. "The missing link between property law and labour law." In XXVI World Congress of Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy. Initia Via, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.17931/ivr2013_sws29_01.
Full textFalci Sousa Rocha Cunha, Juliana. "The intervenue of public law in private law: Brazilian reality." In XXVI World Congress of Philosophy of Law and Social Philosophy. Initia Via, 2015. http://dx.doi.org/10.17931/ivr2013_sws69_03.
Full textReports on the topic "Philosophy of criminal law"
NAVAL JUSTICE SCHOOL NEWPORT RI. Criminal Law Study Guide. Fort Belvoir, VA: Defense Technical Information Center, March 1989. http://dx.doi.org/10.21236/ada210285.
Full textNAVAL JUSTICE SCHOOL NEWPORT RI. Criminal Law Study Guide. Fort Belvoir, VA: Defense Technical Information Center, August 1991. http://dx.doi.org/10.21236/ada243909.
Full textNAVAL JUSTICE SCHOOL NEWPORT RI. Criminal Law Study Guide (Revision). Fort Belvoir, VA: Defense Technical Information Center, August 1998. http://dx.doi.org/10.21236/ada351003.
Full textNAVAL JUSTICE SCHOOL NEWPORT RI. Criminal Law Study Guide. Revision. Fort Belvoir, VA: Defense Technical Information Center, May 1990. http://dx.doi.org/10.21236/ada229204.
Full textShavell, Steven. Economic Analysis of Public Law Enforcement and Criminal Law. Cambridge, MA: National Bureau of Economic Research, May 2003. http://dx.doi.org/10.3386/w9698.
Full textAllen, III, and Norman F. J. Reprisal Under International Law: A Defense to Criminal Conduct? Fort Belvoir, VA: Defense Technical Information Center, March 2009. http://dx.doi.org/10.21236/ada498017.
Full textKofanov, Andrii, and Olena Kofanova. CRIMINAL LAW AND FORENSIC CLASSIFICATION OF SMOOTH-BORE FIREARMS. Intellectual Archive, April 2019. http://dx.doi.org/10.32370/iaj.2079.
Full textDickson, Tiphaine. On the Poverty, Rise, and Demise of International Criminal Law. Portland State University Library, January 2000. http://dx.doi.org/10.15760/etd.2703.
Full textOvcharov, A. V. On criminal law approaches to the assessment of «friendly fire». DOI CODE, 2021. http://dx.doi.org/10.18411/2074-1944-2021-0165.
Full textDastur, Kersas. The Law of Occupation and Criminal Prosecution - A Perspective in Iraq. Fort Belvoir, VA: Defense Technical Information Center, February 2005. http://dx.doi.org/10.21236/ada464556.
Full text