Academic literature on the topic 'Positivisme juridique'
Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles
Consult the lists of relevant articles, books, theses, conference reports, and other scholarly sources on the topic 'Positivisme juridique.'
Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.
You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.
Journal articles on the topic "Positivisme juridique"
Blais, François. "Avortement, éthique sociale et positivisme juridique." Articles 18, no. 2 (August 6, 2007): 63–78. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/027152ar.
Full textTroper, Michel. "Le positivisme juridique." Revue de Synthèse 106, no. 118-119 (June 28, 1985): 187–204. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/19552343-106118119005.
Full textGouttefarde, Fabien. "Positivisme juridique et Modernité." Revue générale de droit 37, no. 1 (October 28, 2014): 7–20. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1027129ar.
Full textBelley, Jean-Guy. "Le pluralisme juridique comme orthodoxie de la science du droit." Canadian journal of law and society 26, no. 2 (August 2011): 257–76. http://dx.doi.org/10.3138/cjls.26.2.257.
Full textLadavac, Nicoletta Bersier. "Le cercle autour de Hans Kelsen." Les cercles viennois de l'entre-deux-guerres 94 (2022): 69–83. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/11ve9.
Full textBadimboli Atibasay, Jean-Faustin. "La double impuissance du positivisme juridique au regard de la normativité du droit international." Revue générale de droit 33, no. 1 (November 26, 2014): 1–38. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/1027542ar.
Full textViala, Alexandre. "Le positivisme juridique : Kelsen et l'héritage kantien." Revue interdisciplinaire d'études juridiques 67, no. 2 (2011): 95. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/riej.067.0095.
Full textKaufmann, Arthur. "Par-delà le droit naturel et le positivisme juridique vers l’herméneutique juridique." Revue interdisciplinaire d'études juridiques 81, no. 1 (2019): 61. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/riej.082.0061.
Full textBELLEY, Jean-Guy. "L’État et la régulation juridique des sociétés globales." Sociologie et sociétés 18, no. 1 (September 30, 2002): 11–32. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/001041ar.
Full textBernatchez, Stéphane. "La controverse doctrinale sur la légitimité du juge constitutionnel canadien." Articles 19, no. 2-3 (November 19, 2008): 89–113. http://dx.doi.org/10.7202/040226ar.
Full textDissertations / Theses on the topic "Positivisme juridique"
Zhiyong, Wang. "Le positivisme juridique dans la Chine ancienne." Paris 10, 1996. http://www.theses.fr/1996PA100136.
Full textAfter have retraced the historical contexts of the birth and the development of legalism, author analyse at first, the philosophical foundation of legalism that is composed of four elements : the empirical epistemology, the postulate of bad human nature, the evolutionism and amoralism. Secondly, author analyse the principles of the legalism from the point of view of general theory of law. Opposed to confucianism, who is build on the moral, the legalism is built upon the law and the sanction, and disregard the morals principles ; the legalism confirm the primacy of the positive law that is the only foundation of social order, and make the law become the essential technique of power. In the final party, author make the comparatives studies on the legalism and the confucianism, on the legalism and the legal positivism, for demonstrating that legalism may be considered one of the legal positivism insofar as legalism is the theory of state of law acceding to which the law is ensemble of the rules supported by the sanction of severe punishment and of the recompense, the validity of the positive law is independent of the moral and of the religion. By contraires, the legalism is ignorant of the epistemological origin established by the european thought between the moral and the law
Bligh, Grégory. "Les bases philosophiques du positivisme juridique de H.L.A. Hart." Thesis, Paris 2, 2016. http://www.theses.fr/2016PA020076.
Full textThis thesis bears on the implicit epistemology and methodological considerations underlying the legal philosophy of H.L.A. Hart (1907-1992), the major representative of XXth century legal positivism in the English speaking world, and Oxford chair of jurisprudence (1952-1968). His work remains little known in France.We will seek to answer the view that Hart might not really have been durably influenced by ordinary language philosophy. We will address these questions by examining a corpus of earlier (overlooked) articles which he published as a young Oxford linguistic philosopher. This “early work” consists of the articles which Hart published before he in was elected to the Oxford chair of jurisprudence. Our view is that the work in general philosophy which he did in this early period is crucial to understand some of the positions which he defends in his legal writings. This thesis will thus show that Hart was active in the epistemological debate opposing the Oxford philosophers and the British representatives of logical atomism and logical empiricism. It will also show that these early positions are carried over into his later jurisprudence, including his major work The Concept of Law (1961).Shedding light on these philosophical foundations of Hart’s legal theory will ultimately allow us to reconstruct the debate opposing his own “analytical positivism” and Continental forms of positivism, such as Hans Kelsen’s normativism or Alf Ross Scandinavian legal realism. It will also allow us to draw important parallels between Hartian legal theory and that of the francophone philosopher Chaïm Perelman
Van, Ouwerkerk Sebastiaan. "Penser les formes d’État : un état de la pensée publiciste française." Thesis, Toulouse 1, 2019. http://www.theses.fr/2019TOU10002/document.
Full textTerreaux, Claude. "Sortir du positivisme juridique aujourd'hui : la solution de Jean Domat." Thesis, Paris 4, 2017. http://www.theses.fr/2017PA040091.
Full textThis doctoral thesis aims to demonstrate that the conception of the law developed by Jean Domat (1625-1696) constitutes an alternative to legal positivism, which is the dominant approach today. Legal positivism impedes any philosophical interrogation; it was unable to oppose totalitarian excesses, and it contributes to the multiplication of texts, which disrupts social cohesion. A theory of the law today should be pervasive and easy to conceptualize. This theory needs to be action-oriented. It needs to inspire all spheres of the Law, be it private law or public law, and should be designed to place all rules imposed by the government under the complete control of the members and leaders of society. This thought should be shareable by everyone, regardless of creed, religion and opinion, hence avoiding communautarian criticism. Moreover, this theory needs to be the result of an examination of the Law itself rather than being deducted from an imposed doctrine. It needs to be able to stand in the way of political abuses and be logical in its developments to be accepted. Jean Domat discovered that the Law is inspired by two principles: “we shall not do to others what we would not like others do to us; we shall do to others what we would like others do to us”. Both principles are in line with the above-mentioned criteria. Jean Domat reconstructs and presents both private law and public law, and shows that they are organized according to these two principles. He presents the whole of private law and demonstrates that the details of the legal relationships between private individuals are all be governed by these two principles. He also shows that they can and should inspire the political action of the Prince. The Prince does not have any particular status: he is subjected to these requirements, as everybody else. Finally, Jean Domat postulates that a subject does not have to obey a law that is not in conformity with these principles. In this doctoral thesis, I show that his thought, that has been forgotten, is highly original for his time. It is also of high relevance in contemporary debate, as it can help us give some new meaning to the law. sunti as doles dolorisintur a consedi de voluptatur molorporum audae voluptio perferovid quiaerferum aut digendus consedi
Brunet, Pierre. "Le concept de représentation dans la théorie de l'État." Paris 10, 1997. http://www.theses.fr/1997PA100136.
Full textIn most of the theoretical constitutional discussions, the concept of representation is treated as fiction because it is assumed that no one could represent another if the first doesn't behave exactly like the second does. Though, to say that an assembly represents people is either, at the best, an erroneous statement that legal science should correct or, at the worst, a lie or an ideology that every one should get rid of. But never comes the question why legal (or constitutional) systems use such concept like representation. That such a question is never asked is for the less amazing from legal theory and, above all, from positivist legal theory (normativist or realistic). Indeed, it is supposed to describe positive law so we should expect that it also describes the use of certain concepts like representation. The fact that postivist legal theory stays far from that concept proceeds from a value judgement which is obviously in contradiction with the purely descriptive methodology. Another position seems possible and would be founded on that simple constatation that legal systems do use concept of representation so the relevant point is then to understand why. It's then necessary to turn classical theoretical question upside down and instead of looking for the legal norms that should be deduced from theory of representation we are concerned with the theory of representation that legal norms need. The method is kelsenian and positivist. The point is not to suggest a new theory of representation but to describe the theory of representation that any legal system produces. The theoretical assumption is that legal systems do not only contain norms but also justifications of these norms (ideologies) that a positivist description must take in account - which doesn't mean that it takes it at face value. The enquiry starts with the end of the old regime, gives a large extent to the french revolution and a shorter to the modern period (the fifth republic is included)
Stylianidis, Nicholas. "Les fondements épistémologiques du positivisme analytique : vers une théorie du droit préinstitutionnelle." Paris 10, 1994. http://www.theses.fr/1994PA100068.
Full textThe thesis examines the epistemological foundations of analytical positivism, i. E. The internal and logical coherence of analytical legal positivism. Analytical legal positivism insists on the separation of law and morality and on the social sources of law. At the same time, according to this theory, a particular importance and emphasis should be given to the study of legal concepts and language. After a systematization of the components (both methodological and substantive) of this theory, the thesis identifies its internal inconsistencies and tries to reconstruct the theory of meaning of legal statements according to an extended interpretation of the presuppositions of analytical legal positivism. This reconstruction cannot offer an adequate solution to the problems of this theory: the social sources thesis of law is methodologically implausible and is not compatible with the normativity thesis of legal positivism, that insists on the normative character of law. Consequently, the thesis stetches an alternative theory of law and suggests that the sources of law are pre-institutional and that the meaning of legal statements is also pre-conventional and referential
Cottereau, Marc. "La séparation entre droit et morale : analyse d'une thèse constitutive du positivisme juridique." Thesis, Toulouse 1, 2018. http://www.theses.fr/2018TOU10036.
Full textLe résumé en anglais n'a pas été communiqué par l'auteur
Giroux, Michel. "Enseigner la common law en français : réquisitoire à l'encontre d'un monopole du positivisme juridique." Acfas-Sudbury, 2005. https://zone.biblio.laurentian.ca/dspace/handle/10219/64.
Full textHardy, Hugo. "Postures et impostures du juspositivisme : Une histoire critique de la notion de positivisme juridique dans la littérature savante anglo-saxonne, XIXe-XXe siècles." Thesis, Université Laval, 2011. http://www.theses.ulaval.ca/2011/28201/28201.pdf.
Full textLerman-Enriquez, Alix. "Esthétique et méthodologie juridique formaliste : pour un symbolisme esthétique appliqué au droit." Paris 10, 2001. http://www.theses.fr/2001PA100177.
Full textBooks on the topic "Positivisme juridique"
Grzegorczyk, Christophe. Le positivisme juridique. Bruxelles: Story-Scientia, 1992.
Find full textJestaz, Philippe, writer of added commentary, ed. Droit naturel et positivisme juridique. Paris]: Dalloz, 2013.
Find full textMacCormick, Neil. Pour une théorie institutionnelle du droit: Nouvelles approches du positivisme juridique. Paris: Librairie générale de droit et de jurisprudence, 1992.
Find full textSintez, Cyril. Le constructivisme juridique: Essai sur l'épistémologie des juristes. Paris: Éditions mare & martin, 2014.
Find full textPollozhani, Bajram. Krijimi i së drejtës dhe roli i teknikës juridike: Aspekte komparative. Prishtinë: Logos-A, 2003.
Find full textG, BLIGH. LES BASES PHILOSOPHIQUES DU POSITIVISME JURIDIQUE DE H.L.A. HART. IUV, 2017.
Find full textG, BLIGH. LES BASES PHILOSOPHIQUES DU POSITIVISME JURIDIQUE DE H.L.A. HART. IUV, 2017.
Find full textNo Place for Ethics: Judicial Review, Legal Positivism, and the Supreme Court of the United States. Rowman & Littlefield Publishers, Incorporated, 2023.
Find full textBook chapters on the topic "Positivisme juridique"
"Mythe et Positivisme Juridique." In Mythes grecs et droit, 163–203. Les Presses de l’Université de Laval, 2017. http://dx.doi.org/10.1515/9782763734811-008.
Full textHerrera, Carlos-Miguel. "Heinrich Triepel et la critique du positivisme juridique à Weimar." In Crise et pensée de la crise en droit, 87–112. ENS Éditions, 2002. http://dx.doi.org/10.4000/books.enseditions.38000.
Full text"Normes juridiques et État d’un point de vue « réaliste »." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, 45–62. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.6.
Full text"Normes juridiques et État chez Duguit et dans la tradition fonctionnaliste." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, 31–44. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.5.
Full text"Le normativisme « impur » de Hart et le droit étatique comme paradigme." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, 63–91. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.7.
Full text"Back Matter." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, 92. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.8.
Full text"Normes juridiques et État dans la Sociological Jurisprudence et chez Ehrlich." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, 23–30. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.4.
Full text"Le normativisme pur de Kelsen et l’identité du droit et de l’État." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, 1–22. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.3.
Full text"Front Matter." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, II—VI. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.1.
Full text"Table of Contents." In Les positivismes juridiques au XXe siècle. Normativismes, sociologismes, réalismes, VII—VIII. Presses de l'Université Laval, 2020. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/j.ctv1h0p41p.2.
Full text