To see the other types of publications on this topic, follow the link: Q Philosophy.

Journal articles on the topic 'Q Philosophy'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the top 50 journal articles for your research on the topic 'Q Philosophy.'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Browse journal articles on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.

1

Wu, Guohua. "Q -measures on Q κ λ". Archive for Mathematical Logic 42, № 2 (2003): 201–4. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s00153-002-0153-z.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Wölfl, Stefan. "Propositional Q-Logic." Journal of Philosophical Logic 31, no. 5 (2002): 387–414. http://dx.doi.org/10.1023/a:1020163602542.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Novirus, Cora. "Q." Multitudes 80, no. 3 (2020): 165. http://dx.doi.org/10.3917/mult.080.0165.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Diem, William Matthew. "Prima Secundae, Q. 18 and De Malo, Q. 2." American Catholic Philosophical Quarterly 91, no. 3 (2017): 447–71. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/acpq2017525119.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Krynicki, Michał, and Hans-Peter Tuschik. "An axiomatization of the logic with the rough quantifier." Journal of Symbolic Logic 56, no. 2 (1991): 608–17. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2274702.

Full text
Abstract:
We consider the language L(Q), where L is a countable first-order language and Q is an additional generalized quantifier. A weak model for L(Q) is a pair 〈, q〉 where is a first-order structure for L and q is a family of subsets of its universe. In case that q is the set of classes of some equivalence relation the weak model 〈, q〉 is called a partition model. The interpretation of Q in partition models was studied by Szczerba [3], who was inspired by Pawlak's paper [2]. The corresponding set of tautologies in L(Q) is called rough logic. In the following we will give a set of axioms of rough log
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Hart, Bradd, and Ziv Shami. "On the type-definability of the binding group in simple theories." Journal of Symbolic Logic 70, no. 2 (2005): 379–88. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1120224718.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractLet T be simple, work in Ceq over a boundedly closed set. Let p Є S(∅) be internal in a quasi-stably-embedded type-definable set Q (e.g., Q is definable or stably-embedded) and suppose (p, Q) is ACL-embedded in Q (see definitions below). Then Aut(p/Q) with its action on pc is type-definable in Ceq over ∅. In particular, if p Є S(∅) is internal in a stably-embedded type-definable set Q, and pc ⋃ Q is stably-embedded, then Aut(p/Q) is type-definable with its action on pc.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Feldman, Norman. "The cylindric algebras of three-valued logic." Journal of Symbolic Logic 63, no. 4 (1998): 1201–17. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2586647.

Full text
Abstract:
In this paper we consider the three-valued logic used by Kleene [6] in the theory of partial recursive functions. This logic has three truth values: true (T), false (F), and undefined (U). One interpretation of U is as follows: Suppose we have two partially recursive predicates P(x) and Q(x) and we want to know the truth value of P(x) ∧ Q(x) for a particular x0. If x0 is in the domain of definition of both P and Q, then P(x0) ∧ Q(x0) is true if both P(x0) and Q(x0) are true, and false otherwise. But what if x0 is not in the domain of definition of P, but is in the domain of definition of Q? Th
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Farkas, Barnabás. "Hechler's Theorem for tall analytic P-ideals." Journal of Symbolic Logic 76, no. 2 (2011): 729–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1305810773.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractWe prove the following version of Hechler's classical theorem: For each partially ordered set (Q, ≤) with the property that every countable subset of Q has a strict upper bound in Q, there is a ccc forcing notion such that in the generic extension for each tall analytic P-ideal (coded in the ground model) a cofinal subset of is order isomorphic to (Q, ≤).
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Gottlob, Georg. "Relativized logspace and generalized quantifiers over finite ordered structures." Journal of Symbolic Logic 62, no. 2 (1997): 545–74. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275546.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractWe here examine the expressive power of first order logic with generalized quantifiers over finite ordered structures. In particular, we address the following problem: Given a family Q of generalized quantifiers expressing a complexity class C, what is the expressive power of first order logic FO(Q) extended by the quantifiers in Q? From previously studied examples, one would expect that FO(Q) captures LC, i.e., logarithmic space relativized to an oracle in C. We show that this is not always true. However, after studying the problem from a general point of view, we derive sufficient co
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Neeman, Itay. "Hierarchies of forcing axioms II." Journal of Symbolic Logic 73, no. 2 (2008): 522–42. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1208359058.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractA truth for λ is a pair 〈Q, ψ〉 so that Q ⊆ Hλ, ψ is a first order formula with one free variable, and there exists B ⊆ Hλ+ such that (Hλ+; ∈, B) ⊨ ψ[Q]. A cardinal λ is , indescribable just in case that for every truth 〈Q, ψ〈 for λ, there exists < λ so that is a cardinal and 〈Q ∩ , ψ) is a truth for . More generally, an interval of cardinals [κ, λ] with κ ≤ λ is indescribable if for every truth 〈Q, ψ〈 for λ, there exists , and π: → Hλ so that is a cardinal, is a truth for , and π is elementary from () into (H; ∈, κ, Q) with id.We prove that the restriction of the proper forcing axio
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
11

Fraga Dantas, Danilo. "Ideal reasoners don’t believe in zombies." Principia: an international journal of epistemology 21, no. 1 (2017): 41–59. http://dx.doi.org/10.5007/1808-1711.2017v21n1p41.

Full text
Abstract:
The negative zombie argument states that p&~q is ideally negatively conceivable and, therefore, possible, what would entail that physicalism is false (Chalmers, 2002, 2010}. In the argument, p is the conjunction of the fundamental physical truths and laws and $q$ is a phenomenal truth. A sentence phi is ideally negatively conceivable iff phi cannot be ruled out a priori on ideal rational reflection. In this paper, I argue that if its premises are true, the negative zombie argument is neither conclusive (valid) nor a priori. First, I argue that the argument is sound iff there exists a finit
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
12

Landver, Avner. "Singular σ-dense trees". Journal of Symbolic Logic 57, № 4 (1992): 1403–16. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275373.

Full text
Abstract:
Let be the least cardinal θ such that MAθ fails, (i.e. MA) implies that is regular. Models for regular with are easy to get (see [Ku1]). Fremlin and Miller proved that cof() > ω [Fr, 41C(d)]. The question of whether it is consistent that be singular was solved, in the affirmative, by Kunen [Ku1]. Kunen used a (θ, θ) strong gap in (ω)/Fin, whose splitting partial order is c.c.c. He showed that if cof(θ) = ω1, and P is a c.c.c. partial order of cardinality < θ that may destroy the strong gap, then there exists another c.c.c. partial order Q, which does not destroy the strong gap, and such
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
13

Hardway, Glenn A. "“Q” SWITCHING." Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 122, no. 2 (2006): 608–13. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1749-6632.1965.tb20241.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
14

Levine, J. "The Q Factor: Modal Rationalism versus Modal Autonomism." Philosophical Review 119, no. 3 (2010): 365–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.1215/00318108-2010-004.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
15

Shami, Ziv. "Coordinatisation by binding groups and unidimensionality in simple theories." Journal of Symbolic Logic 69, no. 4 (2004): 1221–42. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1102022220.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract.In a simple theory with elimination of finitary hyperimaginaries if tp(a) is real and analysable over a definable set Q, then there exists a finite sequence (ai \ i ≤ n*) ⊆ dcleq(a) with an* = a such that for every i ≤ n* if pi = tp(ai/{aj |j < i}) then Aut(pi / Q) is type-definable with its action on . A unidimensional simple theory eliminates the quantifier ∃∞ and either interprets (in Ceq) an infinite type-definable group or has the property that ACL(Q) = C for every infinite definable set Q.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
16

Kosilova, Elena. "The Relationship between Philosophy of Mathematics and Physics of Q. Meillassoux." Ideas and Ideals 12, no. 2-1 (2020): 167–83. http://dx.doi.org/10.17212/2075-0862-2020-12.2.1-167-183.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
17

Omanadze, Roland Sh, та Andrea Sorbi. "A characterization of the δ20 hyperhyperimmune sets". Journal of Symbolic Logic 73, № 4 (2008): 1407–15. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1230396928.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractLet A be an infinite set and let K be creative: we show that K ≤QA if and only if KA. (Here ≤Q denotes Q-reducibility, and is the subreducibility of ≤Q obtained by requesting that Q-reducibility be provided by a computable function f such that Wf(x) ∩ Wf(y) = ∅. if x ≠ y.) Using this result we prove that A is hyperhyperimmune if and only if no subset B of A is s-complete, i.e., there is no subset B of A such that ≤sB, where ≤s denotes s-reducibility, and denotes the complement of K.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
18

Carrier, L. S. "Out-Gunning Skepticism." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 17, no. 3 (1987): 655–57. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00455091.1987.10716460.

Full text
Abstract:
Bredo C. Johnsen1 misconceives my strictures concerning acceptance of the following principle (where ‘p’ stands for any empirical proposition):(1) If A both knows that p and knows that p entails q, then A can come to know that q.Johnsen seems unaware that my criticism was intended to apply only after (1) is made to appear in its most plausible light; that is, only after its consequent is interpreted as: ’It is logically possible for A to know that q.’ Without this interpretation (1) might be dismissed simply on the grounds that A suffers from some physical or psychological disability that prev
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
19

Riis, Søren. "Count( $q$ ) versus the pigeon-hole principle." Archive for Mathematical Logic 36, no. 3 (1997): 157–88. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s001530050060.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
20

Egidi, Lavinia, and Giovanni Faglia. "Double-exponential inseparability of Robinson subsystem Q+." Journal of Symbolic Logic 76, no. 1 (2011): 94–124. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1294170991.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractIn this work a double exponential time inseparability result is proven for a finitely axiomatizable first order theory Q+. The theory, subset of Presburger theory of addition S+, is the additive fragment of Robinson system Q. We prove that every set that separates Q+ from the logically false sentences of addition is not recognizable by any Turing machine working in double exponential time. The lower bound is given both in the non-deterministic and in the linear alternating time models.The result implies also that any theory of addition that is consistent with Q+—in particular any theor
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
21

Bellot, P. "A new proof for Craig's theorem." Journal of Symbolic Logic 50, no. 2 (1985): 395–96. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2274227.

Full text
Abstract:
Craig's theorem is a result about the cardinality of a proper basis for the theory of combinators. Its proof given in [3] was shown to be incomplete by André Chauvin [2]. By using a different approach, we give a very short proof of this theorem. We use the notation of [1].Definition 1. A combinator Q is proper if there exists a natural number n such that for arbitrary variables x1,…,xn we have the following contraction rule:where C is a pure combination of the variables x1,…,xn. Q is to be understood as an abstract symbol, not as a combination of S and K's. Therefore Q comes with a contraction
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
22

Cignoli, Roberto. "Free Q-distributive lattices." Studia Logica 56, no. 1-2 (1996): 23–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/bf00370139.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
23

Bouscaren, E., and E. Hrushovski. "On one-based theories." Journal of Symbolic Logic 59, no. 2 (1994): 579–95. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275409.

Full text
Abstract:
We know from [H1], [H2] that in a stable theory, given a nontrivial locally modular regular type q, one can define a group with generic domination equivalent to q, and that the dependence relation on q can be analyzed in terms of this group. In a stable one-based theory, every regular type is locally modular; hence, this result holds for every nontrivial regular type. We show here that, in fact, in a stable one-based theory, a similar type of construction can be done without the assumption of regularity. More precisely, we show that for any type q, the nontrivial part of q can be analyzed by g
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
24

Newelski, Ludomir. "Scott analysis of pseudotypes." Journal of Symbolic Logic 58, no. 2 (1993): 648–63. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275225.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
25

Tent, Katrin. "A note on the model theory of generalized polygons." Journal of Symbolic Logic 65, no. 2 (2000): 692–702. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2586562.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractUsing projectivity groups, we classify some polygons with strongly minimal point rows and show in particular that no infinite quadrangle can have sharply 2-transitive projectivity groups in which the point stabilizers are abelian. In fact, we characterize the finite orthogonal quadrangles Q(4,2). Q− (5.2) and Q(4,3) by this property. Finally we show that the sets of points, lines and flags of any ℵ1-categorical polygon have Morley degree 1.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
26

JOHNSON, MATTHEW P., and ROHIT PARIKH. "PROBABILISTIC CONDITIONALS ARE ALMOST MONOTONIC." Review of Symbolic Logic 1, no. 1 (2008): 73–80. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1755020308080106.

Full text
Abstract:
One interpretation of the conditional If P then Q is as saying that the probability of Q given P is high. This is an interpretation suggested by Adams (1966) and pursued more recently by Edgington (1995). Of course, this probabilistic conditional is nonmonotonic, that is, if the probability of Q given P is high, and R implies P, it need not follow that the probability of Q given R is high. If we were confident of concluding Q from the fact that we knew P, and we have stronger information R, we can no longer be confident of Q. We show nonetheless that usually we would still be justified in conc
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
27

Beigel, Richard, William Gasarch, Martin Kummer, Georgia Martin, Timothy Mcnicholl, and Frank Stephan. "The complexity of ODDnA." Journal of Symbolic Logic 65, no. 1 (2000): 1–18. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2586523.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractFor a fixed set A. the number of queries to A needed in order to decide a set S is a measure of S's complexity. We consider the complexity of certain sets defined in terms of A:and, for m > 2,where #nA. (x1….. xn) = A(x1) + A(xn)(We identify with , where χA is the characteristic function of A.)If A is a nonrecursive semirecursive set or if A is a jump, we give tight bounds on the number of queries needed in order to decide ODDnA and MODmnA:• ODDnA can be decided with n parallel queries to A, but not with n − 1.• ODDnA can be decided with ⌈log(n + 1)⌉ sequential queries to A but not
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
28

Newelski, Ludomir. "On atomic or saturated sets." Journal of Symbolic Logic 61, no. 1 (1996): 318–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275614.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractAssume T is stable, small and Φ(x) is a formula of L(T). We study the impact on T⌈Φ of naming finitely many elements of a model of T. We consider the cases of T⌈Φ which is ω-stable or superstable of finite rank. In these cases we prove that if T has countable models and Q = Φ(M) is countable and atomic or saturated, then any good type in S(Q) is τ-stable. If T⌈Φ is ω-stable and (bounded, 1-based or of finite rank) with , then we prove that every good p ∈ S(Q) is τ-stable for any countable Q. The proofs of these results lead to several new properties of small stable theories, particular
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
29

Wilson, Robin. "The philamath’s alphabet—Q." Mathematical Intelligencer 30, no. 2 (2008): 80. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/bf02985747.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
30

Erdélyi-Szabó, Miklós. "Decidability of Scott's model as an ordered ℚ-vectorspace". Journal of Symbolic Logic 62, № 3 (1997): 917–24. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275579.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractLet L = 〈<, +, hq, 1〉q∈ℚ where ℚ is the set of rational numbers and hq is a one-place function symbol corresponding to multiplication by q. Then the L-theory of Scott's model for intuitionistic analysis is decidable.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
31

Matet, Pierre, and Janusz Pawlikowski. "Q-pointness, P-pointness and feebleness of ideals." Journal of Symbolic Logic 68, no. 1 (2003): 235–61. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1045861512.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
32

Pessoa Jr., Osvaldo. "The colored-brain thesis." Filosofia Unisinos 22, no. 1 (2021): 84–93. http://dx.doi.org/10.4013/fsu.2021.221.10.

Full text
Abstract:
The “colored-brain thesis”, or strong qualitative physicalism, is discussed from historical and philosophical perspectives. This thesis was proposed by Thomas Case (1888), in a non-materialistic context, and is close to views explored by H. H. Price (1932) and E. Boring (1933). Using Mary’s room thought experiment, one can argue that physicalism implies qualitative physicalism. Qualitative physicalism involves three basic statements: (i) perceptual internalism, and realism of qualia; (ii) ontic physicalism, charaterized as a description in space, time, and scale; and (iii) mind-brain identity
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
33

Newelski, Ludomir. "Flat Morley sequences." Journal of Symbolic Logic 64, no. 3 (1999): 1261–79. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2586628.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractAssume T is a small superstable theory. We introduce the notion of a flat Morley sequence, which is a counterpart of the notion of an infinite Morley sequence in a type p, in case when p is a complete type over a finite set of parameters. We show that for any flat Morley sequence Q there is a model M of T which is τ-atomic over {Q}. When additionally T has few countable models and is 1-based, we prove that within M there is an infinite Morley sequence I, with I ⊂ dcl(Q), such that M is prime over I.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
34

Hrubeš, Pavel. "Theories very close to PA where Kreisel's Conjecture is false." Journal of Symbolic Logic 72, no. 1 (2007): 123–37. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1174668388.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractWe give four examples of theories in which Kreisel's Conjecture is false: (1) the theory PA(-) obtained by adding a function symbol minus, ‘—’, to the language of PA, and the axiom ∀x∀y∀z (x − y = z) ≡ (x = y + z ∨ (x < y ∧ z = 0)); (2) the theory L of integers; (3) the theory PA(q) obtained by adding a function symbol q (of arity ≥ 1) to PA, assuming nothing about q; (4) the theory PA(N) containing a unary predicate N(x) meaning ‘x is a natural number’. In Section 6 we suggest a counterexample to the so called Sharpened Kreisel's Conjecture.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
35

NEIRYNCK, Frans. "The Divorce Saying in Q 16:18." Louvain Studies 20, no. 2 (1995): 201–18. http://dx.doi.org/10.2143/ls.20.2.542305.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
36

Slors, Marc. "Personal Identity, Memory, and Circularity: An Alternative for Q-Memory." Journal of Philosophy 98, no. 4 (2001): 186. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2678477.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
37

van de Graaff, Jan, Hanz D. Niemeyer, and Jan van Overeem. "Beach nourishment, philosophy and coastal protection policy." Coastal Engineering 16, no. 1 (1991): 3–22. http://dx.doi.org/10.1016/0378-3839(91)90050-q.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
38

Alfeld, Christopher P. "Non-branching degrees in the Medvedev lattice of Π10 classes". Journal of Symbolic Logic 72, № 1 (2007): 81–97. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/jsl/1174668385.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractA class is the set of paths through a computable tree. Given classes P and Q, P is Medvedev reducible to Q, P ≤MQ, if there is a computably continuous functional mapping Q into P. We look at the lattice formed by subclasses of 2ω under this reduction. It is known that the degree of a splitting class of c.e. sets is non-branching. We further characterize non-branching degrees, providing two additional properties which guarantee non-branching: inseparable and hyperinseparable. Our main result is to show that non-branching iff inseparable if hyperinseparable if homogeneous and that all un
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
39

Simpson, Stephen G. "Mass Problems and Randomness." Bulletin of Symbolic Logic 11, no. 1 (2005): 1–27. http://dx.doi.org/10.2178/bsl/1107959497.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractA mass problem is a set of Turing oracles. If P and Q are mass problems, we say that P is weakly reducible to Q if every member of Q Turing computes a member of P. We say that P is strongly reducible to Q if every member of Q Turing computes a member of P via a fixed Turing functional. The weak degrees and strong degrees are the equivalence classes of mass problems under weak and strong reducibility, respectively. We focus on the countable distributive lattices ω and s of weak and strong degrees of mass problems given by nonempty subsets of 2ω. Using an abstract Gödel/Rosser incomplete
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
40

Kiymaz, Tufan. "What Gary Couldn’t Imagine." Journal of Philosophical Research 44 (2019): 293–311. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/jpr20191029146.

Full text
Abstract:
In this paper, I propose and defend an antiphysicalist argument, namely, the imagination argument, which draws inspiration from Frank Jackson’s knowledge argument, or rather its misinterpretation by Daniel Dennett and Paul Churchland. They interpret the knowledge argument to be about the ability to imagine a novel experience, which Jackson explicitly denies. The imagination argument is the following. Let Q be a visual phenomenal quality that is imaginable based on one’s phenomenal experience. (1) It is not possible to imagine Q solely based on complete physical knowledge. (2) If it is not poss
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
41

Montminy, Martin. "Knowledge despite falsehood." Canadian Journal of Philosophy 44, no. 3-4 (2014): 463–75. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/00455091.2014.982354.

Full text
Abstract:
I examine the claim, made by some authors, that we sometimes acquire knowledge from falsehood. I focus on two representative cases in which a subject S infers a proposition q from a false proposition p. If S knows that q, I argue, S’s false belief that p is not essential to S’s cognition. S’s knowledge is instead due to S’s belief that p′, a proposition in the neighbourhood of p that S (dispositionally) believes (and knows). S thus knows despite her false belief. The widely accepted and plausible principle that inferential knowledge requires known premises is unscathed.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
42

Atkins, Philip, and Ian Nance. "A Problem for the Closure Argument." International Journal for the Study of Skepticism 4, no. 1 (2014): 36–49. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/22105700-03021102.

Full text
Abstract:
Contemporary discussions of skepticism often frame the skeptic’s argument around an instance of the closure principle. Roughly, the closure principle states that if a subject knows p, and knows that p entails q, then the subject knows q. The main contention of this paper is that the closure argument for skepticism is defective. We explore several possible classifications of the defect. The closure argument might plausibly be classified as begging the question, as exhibiting transmission failure, or as structurally inefficient. Interestingly, perhaps, each of these has been proposed as the corr
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
43

McNicholl, Timothy H. "On the commutativity of jumps." Journal of Symbolic Logic 65, no. 4 (2000): 1725–48. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2695072.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractWe study the following classes:● Q* (r1A1…..rkAk) which is defined to be the collection of all sets that can be computed by a Turing machine that on any input makes a total of ri, queries to Ai, for all i ∈ {1..… k}.● Q(r1A1…..rkAk) which is defined like Q* (r1A1….. rkAk) except that queries to Ai, must be made before queries to Ai+1 for all i ∈ {1….. k – 1}.● QC(r1A1….. rkAk) which is defined like Q{r1A1….. rkAk) except that the Turing machine must halt even if given incorrect answers to some of its queries.We show that if A1 ….. Ak are jumps that are not too close together, then all
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
44

Hella, Lauri, та Kerkko Luosto. "The Beth-closure of ℒ(Qα) is not finitely generated". Journal of Symbolic Logic 57, № 2 (1992): 442–48. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/2275278.

Full text
Abstract:
AbstractWe prove that if ℵα is uncountable and regular, then the Beth-closure of ℒωω(Qα) is not a sublogic of ℒαω(Qn), where Qn is the class of all n-ary generalized quantifiers. In particular, B(ℒωω(Qα)) is not a sublogic of any finitely generated logic; i.e., there does not exist a finite set Q of Lindström quantifiers such that B(ℒωω(Qα)) ≤ ℒωω(Q).
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
45

Tatum, W. Jeffrey. "Q. Cicero, Commentariolum Petitionis 33." Classical Quarterly 52, no. 1 (2002): 394–98. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/cq/52.1.394.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
46

Weisberg, Josh. "The zombie's cogito: Meditations on type-Q materialism." Philosophical Psychology 24, no. 5 (2011): 585–605. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/09515089.2011.562646.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
47

Sitthiwirattham, Thanin, Ghulam Murtaza, Muhammad Aamir Ali, Sotiris K. Ntouyas, Muhammad Adeel, and Jarunee Soontharanon. "On Some New Trapezoidal Type Inequalities for Twice (p, q) Differentiable Convex Functions in Post-Quantum Calculus." Symmetry 13, no. 9 (2021): 1605. http://dx.doi.org/10.3390/sym13091605.

Full text
Abstract:
Quantum information theory, an interdisciplinary field that includes computer science, information theory, philosophy, cryptography, and symmetry, has various applications for quantum calculus. Inequalities has a strong association with convex and symmetric convex functions. In this study, first we establish a p,q-integral identity involving the second p,q-derivative and then we used this result to prove some new trapezoidal type inequalities for twice p,q-differentiable convex functions. It is also shown that the newly established results are the refinements of some existing results in the fi
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
48

Carcopino, Xavier, Didier Raoult, Florence Bretelle, Léon Boubli, and Andreas Stein. "Q Fever during Pregnancy." Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 1166, no. 1 (2009): 79–89. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1749-6632.2009.04519.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
49

MARRIE, THOMAS J. "Q Fever in Octogenarians." Annals of the New York Academy of Sciences 590, no. 1 Rickettsiolog (1990): 266–70. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1749-6632.1990.tb42230.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
50

Koubek, V., and J. Sichler. "On relative universality and Q-universality." Studia Logica 78, no. 1-2 (2004): 279–91. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11225-005-0291-5.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!