To see the other types of publications on this topic, follow the link: The (Aesthetics).

Journal articles on the topic 'The (Aesthetics)'

Create a spot-on reference in APA, MLA, Chicago, Harvard, and other styles

Select a source type:

Consult the top 50 journal articles for your research on the topic 'The (Aesthetics).'

Next to every source in the list of references, there is an 'Add to bibliography' button. Press on it, and we will generate automatically the bibliographic reference to the chosen work in the citation style you need: APA, MLA, Harvard, Chicago, Vancouver, etc.

You can also download the full text of the academic publication as pdf and read online its abstract whenever available in the metadata.

Browse journal articles on a wide variety of disciplines and organise your bibliography correctly.

1

Popovic, Una. "Baumgarten on the sublime: Aesthetics and ethics." Theoria, Beograd 63, no. 3 (2020): 129–39. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo2003129p.

Full text
Abstract:
In this paper, Baumgarten?s account of the sublime will be inspected with regard to the category of aesthetic greatness (magnitudo aesthetica), and in view of his analysis of aesthetic subjectivity. The Sublime is here shown to be the topic within which Baumgarten aims to prove the inner connection between aesthetics and ethics, or, more precisely, that the aesthetic domain is intrinsically related to moral acts and decision-making. My analysis will primarily focus on Baumgarten?s Aesthetics, but it will also include his other works, like Metaphysics and Ethics, as well as the comparison with Pseudo-Longinus?s text On the Sublime. My research should indicate one possible interpretation of Baumgarten?s project, such that it would not discard its purpose, the autonomy of aesthetical domain, but which could, at the same time, determine the relations of aesthetics with other forms of human thought.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
2

Elwazani, Salim. "Purposing aesthetics in historic preservation: advocating, signifying, and interpreting aesthetics." Virtual Archaeology Review 12, no. 24 (January 19, 2021): 66. http://dx.doi.org/10.4995/var.2021.13812.

Full text
Abstract:
<p>Aesthetics is a pillar consideration in historic preservation. Yet, purposing aesthetics for historic preservation ends seems to lag behind the opportunities. Utterly subjective, aesthetics poses challenges for the preservation community worldwide to moderate, accommodate, and purpose aesthetics in heritage programs. The challenges revolve around the assessment of aesthetical purposing in three domains. These domains include the community disposition towards accommodating aesthetics (advocacy), the criteria and strategies for assessing the aesthetic value of historic resources (signification), and, the standards for treating historic resources in preservation projects (interpretation). This study, therefore, assesses the trends for purposing aesthetics in historic preservation thought and practice through three platforms: advocating aesthetics, signifying aesthetics, and interpreting aesthetics. The study completed literature content analysis on aesthetics in general and aesthetics in historic preservation in particular. Further, because of the perspective of the study, the works of international and country preservation programs provided information relevant to advocacy, signification, and interpretation of aesthetics that have been refined by classification, comparison, and exemplification methods. Among others, these works include those of the International Council on Monuments and Sites (ICOMOS) and the U.S. National Historic Preservation Program in the National Park Service. The study culminated with general and platform-specific conclusions. First, as the three proposed platforms (advocacy, signification, and interpretation) maintain structural and serial relationships, they constitute a relevant and feasible framework for assessing aesthetical purposing. Second, as the aesthetical purposing assessment followed a broad, international perspective, the conclusions of the study are commensurate with the selective scope of information used from international and country preservation programs. Third, the contribution to aesthetical purposing at each of the three platforms can be measure only in general, and at times, subjective terms.</p><p><strong>Highlights:</strong></p><ul><li><p>Proposing aesthetical advocacy, aesthetical signification, and aesthetical interpretation as a platform framework to assess the purposing of aesthetics was feasible.</p></li><li><p>As aesthetical purposing was approached from a broad, international perspective, the conclusions of the study commensurate with the selective scope of information used.</p></li><li><p>The contribution to aesthetical purposing at each of the three platforms is hard to measure; however, the indications point to uneven contribution.</p></li></ul>
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
3

Jansen, F. J. Billeskov. "The Aesthete's Aesthetics." Orbis Litterarum 52, no. 6 (December 1997): 373–86. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1600-0730.1997.tb00038.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
4

Hickman, Rechard, and Fraser Smith. "Reviews Editorial: Aesthetics, aesthetic." Journal of Art & Design Education 13, no. 1 (June 1994): 87. http://dx.doi.org/10.1111/j.1476-8070.1994.tb00361.x.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
5

Kirwan, James. "Aesthetics Without the Aesthetic?" Diogenes 59, no. 1-2 (February 2012): 177–83. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0392192112469478.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
6

Ortlieb, Stefan A., Werner A. Kügel, and Claus-Christian Carbon. "Fechner (1866): The Aesthetic Association Principle—A Commented Translation." i-Perception 11, no. 3 (May 2020): 204166952092030. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/2041669520920309.

Full text
Abstract:
Most of the groundbreaking works of Gustav Theodor Fechner (1801–1887), who paved the way for modern experimental psychology, psychophysics, and empirical aesthetics, are so far only available in German. With the first full text translation of Fechner’s article on The Aesthetic Association Principle ( Das Associationsprincip in der Aesthetik), we want to fill in one of the blank spots in the reception of his Aesthetics from Below (Aesthetik von Unten). In his 1866 article, Fechner devises a fundamental principle that accounts for the role of associations in the formation of aesthetic preferences. Based on concrete everyday examples and thought experiments, he demonstrates how aesthetic choices are largely shaped by the observer’s learning history (associative factors) rather than by an object’s formal properties (direct factors). Fechner’s Aesthetic Association Principle has lost nothing of its initial relevance as the role of content and personal meaning is still grossly underrated in theory and practice of empirical aesthetics today.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
7

Onishchenko, E. I. "POLISH AESTHETIC DISCOURSE OF THE 20TH CENTURY: INTERPRETATION OF INTERPRETATIONS." UKRAINIAN CULTURAL STUDIES, no. 1 (2) (2018): 25–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.17721/ucs.2018.1(2).05.

Full text
Abstract:
The article is devoted to the analysis of the Polish aesthetic discourse of the twentieth century and the prospects for its interpretation in the Ukrainian aesthetics, particularly in the works by Kateryna Shevchuk, defended at the department of ethics, aesthetics and culture studies of Taras Shevchenko National University of Kyiv. These research greatly extend the idea of the aesthetic canon of the Polish thought, classically represented by the aesthetics R. Ingarden and W. Tatarkiewicz and reveal the names of virtually unknown in Ukraine Polish scientists, including special interest is the legacy of L. Blaustein, M. Wallis, H. Elzenberg and G. Ossowski. In particular, this perspective covers traditional for the twentieth century aesthetics problems, including psychology of art, collective aesthetic experience, ratio, fantasy, and imagination. Also, new interpretive perspectives of sublime and ugly, aesthetical experience are opened. The theoretical orientations of the Polish scholars, in one way or another, were connected with the cornerstones of the aesthetic science - its subject, the conceptual-categorical apparatus, the structure of aesthetic consciousness, the phenomenon of artistic creativity, the specific nature of art, and others. In the process of conceptual concretization, in the field of Polish aesthetics a number of problems have been rather clearly distinguished, among which the special attention of practically all of its leading representatives has attracted the phenomenon of aesthetical experience. K. Shevchuk’s investigation opens up an opportunity, at least in the format of a secondary interpretation, to join the research of the Polish scholars, whose work proved to be a giant "white spot" for the Ukrainian aestheticians. Introducing actually unexplored concepts Polish scientists to the modern Ukrainian aesthetic theory not only facilitates the opening of "unknown pages" in the history of the twentieth century aesthetics, but also makes actual mark of new approaches to the analysis of classical problems, the relevance of which will never be a subject of doubt.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
8

Scott, Sarah. "From Genius to Taste." Journal of Jewish Thought & Philosophy 25, no. 1 (May 23, 2017): 110–30. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/1477285x-12341281.

Full text
Abstract:
I reconstruct the aestheticism of Martin Buber in order to provide a new way of framing his moral philosophy and development as a thinker. The evolution of Buber’s thought does not entail a shift from aesthetics to ethics, but a shift from one aspect of aesthetics to another, namely, from taking genius to be key to social renewal, to taking taste to be key. I draw on Kantian aesthetics to show the connection between Buber’s aesthetic concerns and his moral concerns, and to defend the notion that a certain aesthetic orientation may be just what is needed for moral response.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
9

Stige, Brynjulf. "The Aesthetic or Multiple Aesthetics?" Nordic Journal of Music Therapy 17, no. 1 (January 2008): 25–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/08098130809478193.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
10

Pattison, George. "KIERKEGAARD: AESTHETICS AND ‘THE AESTHETIC’." British Journal of Aesthetics 31, no. 2 (1991): 140–51. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/bjaesthetics/31.2.140.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
11

Sattler, Janyne. "Middleway aesthetics: an aesthetical way to say nothing about aesthetics." Revista de Filosofia Aurora 27, no. 40 (April 28, 2015): 375. http://dx.doi.org/10.7213/aurora.27.040.ao06.

Full text
Abstract:
This is a very brief sketch on Wittgenstein’s “middle” writings about aesthetical appreciation and aesthetical attitude concerning the objects of art. Even if it takes the Tractarian conception of ‘aesthetics’ as a starting point, the paper is focused on Wittgenstein’s (second-hand) class-notes taken from his Lectures on Aesthetics and a very specific remark reported by Moore, brought from the Philosophical Occasions, where “reasons” for aesthetical persuasion and correction are said to be like those offered in “discussions in a court of law”. At the end, not much is left for aesthetical appreciation and for aestheticsitself but a certain kind of contextual, circumstantial “appeal to the judge”.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
12

Ortlieb, Stefan A., and Claus-Christian Carbon. "Kitsch and Perception: Towards a New ‘Aesthetic from Below’." Art and Perception 7, no. 1 (March 6, 2019): 1–26. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/22134913-00001091.

Full text
Abstract:
Although kitsch is one of the most important concepts of twentieth-century art theory, it has gone widely unnoticed by empirical aesthetics. In this article we make a case that the study of kitsch is of considerable heuristic value for both empirical aesthetics and art perception. As a descriptive term, kitsch appears like a perfect example of hedonic fluency. In fact, the frequently invoked opposition of kitsch and art reflects two types of aesthetic experience that can be reliably distinguished in terms of processing dynamics: a disfluent one that promises new insights but requires cognitive elaboration (art), and a fluent one that consists of an immediate, unreflective emotional response but leaves us with what we already know (kitsch). Yet as a derogatory word, kitsch draws our attention to a general disregard for effortless emotional gratification in modern Western aesthetics that can be traced back to eighteenth-century Rationalism. Despite all efforts of Pop Art to embrace kitsch and to question normative values in art, current models of aesthetic liking—including fluency-based ones—still adhere to an elitist notion of Modern art that privileges style over content and thereby excludes what is essential not only for popular taste and Postmodern art but also for premodern artistic production: emotionally rich content. Revisiting Fechner’s (Vorschule der Aesthetik, 1876) criticism of highbrow aesthetics we propose a new aesthetic from below (Aesthetik von Unten) that goes beyond processing characteristics by taking content- and context-related associations into account.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
13

Fokeeva, Mariia Petrovna. "Sublime in the aesthetics of trauma." Философская мысль, no. 3 (March 2020): 68–73. http://dx.doi.org/10.25136/2409-8728.2020.3.32311.

Full text
Abstract:
The subject of this article is the concept of sublime. The author examines which transformations has experiences the aesthetic theory of sublime since the XVIII century. In the context of aesthetics of trauma, sublime is a specific form of aesthetical experience that emerges in the context of encountering traumatic experience of the history, where the key concomitant affect is horror. The forms of sublime, associated with encountering the historical trauma, are immeasurable by their influence, as the scales of catastrophe cannot be assessed rationally, and the experience of historical violence discredits the possibility of subjective routine. Research methodology is structured on the philosophical-aesthetic approach. Which is based on analysis of the concepts of sublime and negative sublime. The author comes to the conclusion that sublime in the XX century experiences crisis related to reconsideration of the modernistic values. However, discipline associate with the aesthetic reconsideration of traumatic historical events &ndash; the aesthetics of trauma, rehabilitates the concept of sublime, because representation of the traumatic through referring to sublime, opens an opportunity to comprehend the traumatic experience and overcome it.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
14

DOLGOVA, Elena D. "AESTHETICS OF ANONYMOUS ARCHITECTURE." Urban construction and architecture 6, no. 2 (June 15, 2016): 91–95. http://dx.doi.org/10.17673/vestnik.2016.02.17.

Full text
Abstract:
The article examines the anonymous architecture in terms of aesthetic knowledge. A parallel between the categories of classical aesthetics - a beautiful / ugly, and the categories of architectural activity in the Vitruvian paradigm professional / anonymous is drawn. Traced the background and process of incorporating objects anonymous architecture in non-classical aesthetic field through poetization everyday life, the emergence of technical aesthetics, aesthetics and functionalism of modernism. Non-classical aesthetics characterize objects anonymous architecture using parakategory daily, physicality, thing. We present the aesthetic characteristics of the anonymous architecture using the categories developed in the traditional aesthetics of eastern cultures - wabi, sabi, sibui and eugen. A parallel between the perception of the aesthetics and simplicity of anonymity is drawn.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
15

Loginova, Marina V. "Ethno-aesthetics in the system ethnic culture: theoretical and methodological aspect." Finno-Ugric World 13, no. 2 (July 12, 2021): 169–79. http://dx.doi.org/10.15507/2076-2577.013.2021.02.169-179.

Full text
Abstract:
Introduction. The article deals with the study of theoretical and methodological foundations of ethno-aesthetics as a “cultural code” of an ethnos through a systematic approach to solving the problem of the ratio of ethno-culture and ethno-aesthetics. The aim of the study is a philosophical analysis of ethno-aesthetics to determine the semantic potential of the symbolic capital of ethnic culture. Materials and Methods. The logic of the research, ascending from the abstract (definition of ethno-aesthetics) to the exact (ethno-futurism), is based on a systemic approach. It distinguishes the following methods: dialectical (ethno-aesthetics at the level of the singular, particular and universal), comparative-historical (transformation of ethno-aesthetic values); structural and functional (ethno-aesthetics as an open system of aesthetic values that serve as “markers” of ethnic originality). Results and Discussion. The author denotes the theoretical and methodological aspects of ethno-aesthetics in the modern conditions of being of an ethnos: ethno-aesthetic values, aesthetic ontology of ethnos, expression in ethno-aesthetics of the “spirit of a people”. In the ethnic world-picture the expression of the concept “spirit of the people” allows to highlight the levels of ethno-aesthetics in ethnoculture: substantial (aesthetic consciousness, aesthetic values that reflect/express the “spirit of a people”); functional-historical (transforming system of aesthetic relations and aesthetic experience of an ethnos). The author notes the relationship of ethno-aesthetic values with mentality, the “spirit of a people”, the deep layers of ethnic consciousness (traditions, rites, beliefs, mythological representations, archetypes), art as a system of creating symbolic images. The dialectics of single, special and universal with regard to aesthetic values distinguishes ethno-aesthetics as the level of being of special, which at the same time combines (values and creative potential of an ethnos in world exploration) and determines the specifics of understanding and interpretation by an ethnos the basic values (the beautiful, the tragic, the comic, etc.) and its fixation in the language. The source of aesthetic ontology is the experiencing by an ethnos life, nature, labour, creativity, which have creative and harmonizing potential. Conclusion. The author interprets ethno-aesthetics as an integral part of aesthetics, which creates a philosophical theory of an ethnos aesthetic relationship to the world (nature, art, labour), reflects the process of formation and development of aesthetic sensuality and aesthetic consciousness, the value of the world.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
16

Cova, Florian, and Nicolas Pain. "Can Folk Aesthetics Ground Aesthetic Realism?" Monist 95, no. 2 (2012): 241–63. http://dx.doi.org/10.5840/monist201295214.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
17

Woods, Walter A. "Parameters of Aesthetic Objects: Applied Aesthetics." Empirical Studies of the Arts 9, no. 2 (July 1991): 105–14. http://dx.doi.org/10.2190/7d3x-03g1-aguv-w417.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
18

Rancière, Jacques. "The Aesthetic Dimension: Aesthetics, Politics, Knowledge." Critical Inquiry 36, no. 1 (January 2009): 1–19. http://dx.doi.org/10.1086/606120.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
19

Dourley, John. "Jung, a mystical aesthetic, and abstract art." International Journal of Jungian Studies 7, no. 1 (January 2, 2015): 4–18. http://dx.doi.org/10.1080/19409052.2014.924687.

Full text
Abstract:
On the question of aesthetics, Jung makes a clear distinction between aestheticism and aesthetics. He dismissed the former as lacking substance and moral commitment, but allows that his psychology can never usurp but can contribute to a depth aesthetic. On close examination, this aesthetic rests on the manifestation of the archetypal in all forms of creativity. As such, it is closely related to the spiritual and religious. Modern expressionist and abstract art was consciously influenced by the apophatic mystical tradition to which Jung himself was drawn. Kandinsky and Arp are significant representatives of this tradition who were influenced by mystical experience – especially that of Jacob Boehme, one of Jung's key intellectual ancestors. The paper works to identify the rudiments of a Jungian aesthetic and show its compatibility with the work and theory of Kandinsky, Arp and the expressionist/abstract project.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
20

Fischer-Lescano, Andreas. "Sociological Aesthetics of Law." Law, Culture and the Humanities 16, no. 2 (July 1, 2016): 268–93. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/1743872116656777.

Full text
Abstract:
Aesthetic theory has the potential to develop a sensorium for the rational and arational forces of law. But the aesthetic knowledge of law is underdeveloped. That is why this article proposes a self-reflective sociological aesthetics of law that is capable of acknowledging human and social forces. The article unfolds its argument in three steps: first, it outlines the main approaches in the field of “law and aesthetics”; second, it connects these approaches in legal aesthetics with sociological and philosophical discussions on aesthetics; and, third, it suggests what distinctive contributions such a connection could make to jurisprudence and legal practice.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
21

Hermerén, Göran. "Notions of the Aesthetic and of Aesthetics: Essays on Art, Aesthetics and Culture." British Journal of Aesthetics 58, no. 2 (November 28, 2017): 212–15. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayw093.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
22

Kreft, Lev. "How to defend aesthetics?" SAJ - Serbian Architectural Journal 7, no. 2 (2015): 27–36. http://dx.doi.org/10.5937/saj1501027k.

Full text
Abstract:
Milan Damnjanović (1924-1994) published his aesthetic opus in the context of (Yugoslav) Marxist "overcoming" (Aufhebung) of aesthetics and of aesthetics' self-criticism expressed as the "crisis of aesthetics". To oppose both of these critical positions and at the same time reform aesthetics' ability to treat all aesthetic phenomena, but still keep art in special focus, he introduced the problem of immediacy of experience of the world by a human being. In his article "The Problem of Immediacy and Mediation in Marx's Thought" (1970) Damnjanović wanted to demonstrate the primacy of aesthetic dimension in immediacy and immediate mediation/reflection which can support philosophy's legitimate claim to organize it as an open system, and aesthetics' solidity as a discipline of such system. To achieve this purpose, he introduced an intertwined argumentation which combines his reading of Marx's philosophy of labour from Paris Manuscripts and from Capital with Helmut Plessner's esthesiology and Paul Valery's esthésique. To revisit Damnjanović's defence of the Whole, of philosophical systematicity, and of aesthetics' autonomous position as a discipline is an opportunity to argue that he pointed into the right direction, be it in taking Plessner and Valéry for support, or, in taking fundamental philosophical problem of immediacy/mediation as a foundation stone of the status of aesthetics.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
23

Wilson, Alan T. "The Virtue of Aesthetic Courage." British Journal of Aesthetics 60, no. 4 (August 1, 2020): 455–69. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayaa022.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract Theorists have recently been exploring the prospects for a virtue-centred approach to aesthetics. Virtue aesthetics encourages a re-focusing of philosophical attention onto the aesthetic character traits of agents, in the same way that virtue ethics and virtue epistemology have encouraged us to focus on moral and intellectual traits. In this paper, I aim to contribute to the development of virtue aesthetics by discussing aesthetic courage, the aesthetic analogue of one of the most widely acknowledged moral virtues. In addition to proposing an account of the nature of this trait, I also argue that aesthetic courage is vital for any sort of aesthetically virtuous life. It is not possible to possess any aesthetic virtue without possessing aesthetic courage. It is important, therefore, for any future development of virtue aesthetics to acknowledge the central importance of aesthetic courage.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
24

Novakovic, Marko. "Renewal of aisthesis in contemporary aesthetics." Theoria, Beograd 62, no. 2 (2019): 17–34. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo1902017n.

Full text
Abstract:
The main subject of this work is the new aesthetics of atmospheres promoted in the last decades of 20th century by Gernot B?hme. Aesthetics of the atmospheres is a consequence of revival of aesthesis in contemporary aesthetics. The concept of atmospheres changes the model of perception from mechanical-cognitivistic to pathic and existential: perception is not grasping the sensitive qualities of things, but bodily sensing ourselves in the presence of atmospheres filling space or environment. Traditional concept of aisthesis and aesthetics as a science of sensitive knowledge provides a model for contemporary aesthetics and renewal of interest for sensitivity and perception in problems related to nature and aestheticized life world and politics. The task of contemporary aesthetic theory is to analyse the full range aesthetic work and aesthetic experiences using concept of atmospheres, not only related to works of art, but to nature and everyday life as well. In the context of contemporary theories of appreciation of nature, this type of aesthetic theory belongs to aesthesical model. According to this model, sensing oneself in the presence of aesthetic object in nature or art is the principal feature of every aesthetic experience.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
25

Süner, Ahmet. "A critical evaluation of Heidegger’s criticism of aesthetics in ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’." Journal of European Studies 47, no. 1 (November 1, 2016): 21–33. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0047244116676686.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper examines and critiques Heidegger’s repudiation of aesthetics in his essay ‘The Origin of the Work of Art’ and claims that his alternative approach to artworks in the essay must be understood as a theory of aesthetics and, more particularly, of aesthetic use, which delineates the inseparability of senses and sensations. The paper analyses Heidegger’s explicit remarks on aesthetics in the epilogue, discusses his criticism of the aesthetic thing-interpretation at the beginning of the essay and concludes with some critical observations on Heidegger’s own aesthetics. While critical of Heidegger’s separation of the equipment from the artwork, the paper claims that Heidegger’s significant contribution to the field of aesthetics must be sought in his focus on the attenuation of the subjective element in aesthetic experience.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
26

Biskoivski, Lawrence J. "Politics Versus Aesthetics: Arendt's Critiques of Nietzsche and Heidegger." Review of Politics 57, no. 1 (1995): 59–89. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s0034670500019938.

Full text
Abstract:
Several recent commentaries on Hannah Arendt's political thought have suggested strong connections and affinities between Arendt and Nietzsche or between Arendt and various later Nietzschean, aestheticist, or postmodernist thinkers. But a close reading of Arendt's critiques of Nietzsche and Heidegger suggests that an overemphasis on the more Nietzschean or aesthetic aspects of Arendt's work risks obscuring some vital distinctions Arendt makes or preserves concerning politics and aesthetics. More significantly, the Nietzschean or aestheticist interpretation of Arendt tends to conceal or distort Arendt's actual, highly original, and more promising response to various facets of the modern political condition.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
27

Cutting, James E. "Goldilocks Aesthetics." Projections 14, no. 2 (June 1, 2020): 66–74. http://dx.doi.org/10.3167/proj.2020.140206.

Full text
Abstract:
Much of aesthetics is based in psychological responses. Yet seldom have such responses—couched in empirically based psychological terms—played a central role in the discussion of movie aesthetics. Happily, Todd Berliner’s Hollywood Aesthetic: Pleasure in American Cinema does just that. This commentary discusses some history and some twists and turns behind Berliner’s analysis.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
28

Grubor, Nebojsa. "The relation between the beauty and the sublime in Hartmann′s aesthetics." Theoria, Beograd 63, no. 3 (2020): 159–67. http://dx.doi.org/10.2298/theo2003159g.

Full text
Abstract:
The text examines the relationship between the beauty and the sublime in Hartmann?s aesthetics. According to the basic assumption of Hartmann?s aesthetics, the sublime, like all other aesthetic values, are subordinated to the beauty. The text shows that the relationship between the beauty and the sublime in Hartmann?s aesthetics is complex and that beauty formally includes the sublime, but that the sublime in terms of fixing aesthetic content is the core of aesthetic issues.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
29

Du, Wei. "Aesthetic utilitarianism: heritage of modern Chinese aesthetics." Neohelicon 43, no. 2 (August 31, 2016): 529–42. http://dx.doi.org/10.1007/s11059-016-0359-4.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
30

Wilson, R. "Aesthetics and its Discontents * The Aesthetic Unconscious." British Journal of Aesthetics 51, no. 1 (April 25, 2010): 103–5. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/aesthj/ayq015.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
31

Nadin, Mihai. "Emergent Aesthetics: Aesthetic Issues in Computer Arts." Leonardo. Supplemental Issue 2 (1989): 43. http://dx.doi.org/10.2307/1557943.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
32

Dolapçıoğlu, Sevda, Burcu Gürkan, and Memet Karakuş. "Aesthetics and aesthetic creativity in social studies." Pegem Eğitim ve Öğretim Dergisi 9, no. 3 (July 20, 2019): 913–44. http://dx.doi.org/10.14527/pegegog.2019.029.

Full text
Abstract:
This study’s aim is to investigate the primary school teachers’ views on the applications of aesthetic and aesthetic creativity in social studies class. It was designed as a phenomenological study as one of the qualitative research methods. The participants of the study consisted of 8 primary school teachers working in schools with different socio-economic substructure in Adana and Hatay in the 2017-2018 academic year. The data were collected through semi-structured interview form, and analysed following content analysis method. The findings of the study revealed that teachers conceptualize the concept of aesthetic in different ways; they consider that aesthetic creativity is as important as scientific creativity; that aesthetic education contributes to mental and emotional development of the students; that social studies class is effective in gaining creativity; and accordingly, they have included aesthetic education in their courses. The findings of the study revealed that teachers conceptualize the concept of aesthetic in different ways; that they consider that aesthetic creativity is as important as scientific creativity; they believe aesthetic education contributes to mental and emotional development of the students; that they think social studies class is effective in gaining creativity; and, therefore, they include aesthetic education in various ways in their courses.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
33

Middendorf, Ulrike. "AESTHETICS OF EMOTION AND AESTHETIC EMOTION INXUNZI." Monumenta Serica 59, no. 1 (December 2011): 17–71. http://dx.doi.org/10.1179/mon.2011.59.1.002.

Full text
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
34

Loesberg, Jonathan. "Kant's Aesthetics and Wilde Form." Victoriographies 1, no. 1 (May 2011): 79–95. http://dx.doi.org/10.3366/vic.2011.0008.

Full text
Abstract:
Although Wilde was convicted of Gross Indecency, not of having written questionable literature, critics frequently take his trial as a trial of his literature and his theories, and, in a sense, they are oddly enough right since, at key moments, the difficult of reading Wilde's writing becomes manifest in the difficulty of reading what occurs in the trials. That reading difficulty results from the alignment between Wilde's aestheticism and the ostensibly straighter Kantian aesthetics, a theory Wilde queered only by clarifying its paradoxes. Through a comparative reading of Kant's and Wilde's theories of natural and aesthetic beauty and the manifestation of Wilde's theory in The Picture of Dorian Gray (1891), this article will show how the ambiguities in Wilde's trial result from his insistence on a connection between his theoretical paradoxes and what he called his perverse desires, a connection that enriches both aesthetic theory and our understanding of the cultural significance of his trial.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
35

Agung, Lingga, and Novian Denny Nugraha. "Digital Culture and Instagram: "Aesthetics for All?"." IMOVICCON Conference Proceeding 1, no. 1 (July 3, 2019): 93–98. http://dx.doi.org/10.37312/imoviccon.v1i1.7.

Full text
Abstract:
Aesthetics is the study of beauty but in a cultural discourse is a representation of cultural expressions that mark its position in social reality. Thus, aesthetics is not a subjective expression of culture but rather a mechanism by which beauty is produced and distributed. The mechanism continues to operate even in a wider landscape such as in multidimensional technological space. This has resulted the aesthetic deconstruction because the norm operates differently. Instagram, which attracted latest generation, has birth a digital culture oriented to the new aesthetic visual forms. The aesthetic visual on Instagram constructed through visual production that is continuously interwoven with one another. The mechanism of cultural production in Instagram tends to deconstruct aesthetics as a norm. The public is more oriented to actions rather than philosophical contemplation. However, the mechanism of culture produces the discourse of aesthetics in Instagram still needs to explore. This research is important because we facing ‘loss of ideological and historical awareness’ of the aesthetics and aesthetics are the alternative to explore the nature of humanity. This research tries to explain how the aesthetics mechanism works on Instagram by virtual ethnography method and Bourdieu's ‘Capital Culture’ theory.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
36

Zhang, Pengcheng, Yezi Chen, Yiran Zhu, and Haibin Wang. "Eye region as a predictor of holistic facial aesthetic judgment: An eventrelated potential study." Social Behavior and Personality: an international journal 49, no. 1 (January 6, 2021): 1–13. http://dx.doi.org/10.2224/sbp.9660.

Full text
Abstract:
Event-related potentials (ERP) play an important role in the early detection of emotional arousal. Previous studies of aesthetics have shown that the positive component appearing around 200 ms after stimulus (P2) and the larger late positive component (LPC) are closely related to the early stage of aesthetic judgment. We investigated the temporal features of facial aesthetic judgment on the basis of facial features by using the ERP technique. Participants were instructed to predict holistic face aesthetic level based on the regions of eyes, mouth, or nose. Behavioral results show that holistic score predictions based on the eye region were no different to holistic aesthetic ratings. The ERP analysis results show that beautiful eyes and faces elicited a smaller P2 amplitude and LPC amplitude when judging the holistic aesthetic. The P2 effect of facial aesthetics may reflect automatic processing of facial aesthetics and the difference in LPC may be related to motivational attention to facial aesthetics. Because of the similar ERP effect between the holistic facial aesthetic judgment and the aesthetic judgment of eye region, this region may play a significant role in predicting holistic facial aesthetics. The implication is that the eyes are not only a window to the soul, but also a benchmark of beauty.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
37

Al-Salam, Nadia A., Ahmed A. Al-Jaberi, and Ahmed S. Al-Khafaji. "Measuring of Subjective and Objective Aesthetics in Planning and Urban Design." Civil Engineering Journal 7, no. 9 (September 1, 2021): 1557–68. http://dx.doi.org/10.28991/cej-2021-03091743.

Full text
Abstract:
The article includes the concept of aesthetics through what has been dealt with in the literature by philosophers and researchers who have addressed this concept in an attempt to derive indicators of aesthetics. The article adopted a descriptive and analytical methodology by reviewing recent literature on the concept of aesthetics and its relation to urban planning and design issues. Many subjective and objective aesthetics indicators have been identified, some of which are classified under real aesthetics, and some under fake aesthetics. The indicators were applied to the Kufa Mosque complex and Sahla Mosque complex as a comparative case study. It was found that the indicators of real aesthetics have a higher weight in determining the final aesthetic judgment on the complex form versus the fake indicators, which in turn reinforced the weighting of the subjective aspect over the objective. This was consistent with the answer to the question directed to the sample about which complexes are more aesthetic. The answer was that the Kufa Mosque complex is most aesthetically. This was proven by the questions directed in the questionnaire, which outweighed the real aesthetic indicators for the Kufa Mosque complex. As for the results of analyzing the indicators of fake aesthetic were equal, as each complex achieved higher values in three indicators. Doi: 10.28991/cej-2021-03091743 Full Text: PDF
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
38

Koskinen, Ilpo. "Agonistic, Convivial, and Conceptual Aesthetics in New Social Design." Design Issues 32, no. 3 (July 2016): 18–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.1162/desi_a_00396.

Full text
Abstract:
This paper explores aesthetics in what it calls new social design. It asks, “How can designers work with aesthetics when the main design object is social, and traditional object-bound aesthetic concepts lose their validity.” It describes three approaches to aesthetics: agonistic, which sees aesthetics as a way to lure people to interact with controversial content; convivial, which finds aesthetics in community interactions; and conceptual, which does away with aesthetics. All these have precedents in art.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
39

Woods, Walter A., and Thomas C. Padgett. "Aesthetics Applied to Fashion Apparel." Empirical Studies of the Arts 5, no. 1 (January 1987): 15–30. http://dx.doi.org/10.2190/g0eu-c5ec-ggq5-2ly7.

Full text
Abstract:
An apparently ambiguous status for aesthetics in fashion theory is noted and discussed and an applied aesthetics approach to supplement the current communications theory approach is proposed. Two classes of aesthetic properties—intrinsic formal and extrinsic symbolic content—are discussed in terms of stimulus properties. Certain stimulus properties are used in an experiment in which it is demonstrated that aesthetic properties can be identified and used in evaluating fashion apparel. The findings suggest that when aesthetic criteria are considered in fashion theory, classical fashion concepts such as taste leadership require reevaluation.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
40

Lamb, David. "Animals, Ethics and Aesthetics." Journal of Applied Animal Ethics Research 1, no. 1 (March 25, 2019): 66–87. http://dx.doi.org/10.1163/25889567-12340006.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract Mainstream theories which argue for enhanced ethical status of animals with appeals to sentience or intelligence have depicted aesthetics in a negative sense. This paper supports a different outlook. We explore reasons why aesthetic appreciation of animals is portrayed as subjective and sentimental, concerned only with superficial and external features. Aesthetic qualities, as understood here, are not intended as criteria for admission to a moral community or as a guide for veterinary professionals when prioritizing therapy. The case for measuring the extent of an animal’s beauty or attractiveness in order to establish its entitlement to moral status or rights is a non-starter. Nevertheless, aesthetic traditions, we argue, play a significant role in our moral response to animals and objectives to protect them. As a corrective to misunderstandings regarding the status of aesthetics in deliberation about moral obligations to animals a case for the integration of ethics and aesthetics is developed.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
41

Daeng Pasiga, Burhanuddin Daeng, Rasmidar Samad, and Rini Pratiwi. "Relationship of Oral Aesthetic Assessment according to Self Perception with Oral Malocclusion Condition of High School Students in Sidrap District, South Sulawesi Indonesia." Brazilian Dental Science 22, no. 4 (October 31, 2019): 450–57. http://dx.doi.org/10.14295/bds.2019.v22i4.1712.

Full text
Abstract:
Self-perception of dental aesthetics needs to be considered in planning orthodontic treatment because it is known that everyone has a self-perception of different oral esthetic conditions. Objective: To assess the state of malocclusion based on self-perception of dental aesthetics using the Oral Aesthetic Subjective Impact Score (OASIS); to determine the relationship of self-perceptions of oral aesthetics and the state of malocclusion from the results of clinical examinations using the Dental Aesthetic Index (DAI). Material and Methods: Research subjects were middle school students aged between 14-18 years as many as 187 students. For oral aesthetic assessment using the OASIS index questionnaire, and to evaluate the aesthetic and anatomical components of the malocclusion clinic using the Dental Aesthetic Index (DAI). Results: The prevalence of malocclusion according to Dental Aesthetic Index (DAI) showed that mild / normal malocclusion (59.9%), moderate malocclusion (33.4%), severe malocclusion (5.7%), and very severe malocclusion (1%). The prevalence of self-perception of oral aesthetics was 54.6% judging good. The results of the analysis with logistic regression tests showed that there was a significant (p<0.001) relationship between self-perception of oral aesthetics using the OASIS index and malocclusion status using the DAI index. Conclusion: Based on the results of this study, there was a significant relationship (p <0.01) between oral aesthetic self perception and malocclusion status of high school students.KeywordsOral aesthetic perception; Oral aesthetic subjective impact score; Dental aesthetic index.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
42

Tribot, Anne-Sophie, Julie Deter, and Nicolas Mouquet. "Integrating the aesthetic value of landscapes and biological diversity." Proceedings of the Royal Society B: Biological Sciences 285, no. 1886 (September 5, 2018): 20180971. http://dx.doi.org/10.1098/rspb.2018.0971.

Full text
Abstract:
As a cultural ecosystem service, the aesthetic value of landscapes contributes to human well-being, but studies linking biodiversity and ecosystem services generally do not account for this particular service. Therefore, congruence between the aesthetic perception of landscapes, ecological value and biodiversity remains poorly understood. Here, we describe the conceptual background, current methodologies and future challenges of assessing landscape aesthetics and its relationship with biodiversity. We highlight the methodological gaps between the assessment of landscape aesthetics, ecological diversity and functioning. We discuss the challenges associated with connecting landscape aesthetics with ecological value, and the scaling issues in the assessment of human aesthetics perception. To better integrate aesthetic value and ecological components of biodiversity, we propose to combine the study of aesthetics and the understanding of ecological function at both the species and landscape levels. Given the urgent need to engage society in conservation efforts, this approach, based on the combination of the aesthetic experience and the recognition of ecological functioning by the general public, will help change our culture of nature and promote ecologically oriented conservation policies.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
43

Dai, Chuang. "Philosophical-aesthetic reflection in China in the century: Wang Guowei and Zong Baihua." Философская мысль, no. 12 (December 2020): 15–29. http://dx.doi.org/10.25136/2409-8728.2020.12.34614.

Full text
Abstract:
&nbsp; This article is dedicated to examination of the philosophical-aesthetic reflection in China in the XX century, and the impact of European aesthetics upon the development and transformation of the traditional Chinese aesthetics. The article employs the method of historical and cultural with elements of structural analysis of aesthetic text of the modern Chinese philosophers. In the XX century, a number of Chinese thinkers made attempts of reforming the traditional Chinese aesthetics, complementing it with the viewpoint of European philosophy. The article examines the paramount aesthetic thoughts of the modern Chinese philosophers Wang Guowei and Zong Baihua, and determines the impact of European philosophy upon them. The scientific novelty of this study lies in assessing the impact of the concepts of European aesthetics upon self-reflection and development of Chinese aesthetics in the context of cross-cultural problematic. It is demonstrated that Chinese modern aesthetics in many ways retains its connection with the tradition, which determines its specificity and imparts peculiar semantic symbolism. The conclusion is made that in the XX century, Chinese philosophers sought to complement the existing traditional Chinese reflection on art, which is based mostly on the ideas of Taoism and Buddhism, with what can be referred to as the Western viewpoint, associated with a scientific approach and scientific interpretation. Another vector in the area of humanistic understanding of the phenomenon of art was related to the attempts of interpretation of the European aesthetic thought from through the prism of Chinese traditional philosophy. The philosopher Wang Guowei tried to incorporate the European aesthetics into the scientific problematic of China. The philosopher Zong Baihua wanted to synthesize the Chinese and European aesthetic theories, and create what he believed is the modern Chinese aesthetics. &nbsp;
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
44

Saito, Yuriko. "Everyday aesthetics and world-making." Contrastes. Revista Internacional de Filosofía 25, no. 3 (January 19, 2021): 35–54. http://dx.doi.org/10.24310/contrastescontrastes.v25i3.11567.

Full text
Abstract:
The project of world-making is carried out not only by professional world-makers, such as designers, architects, and manufacturers. We are all participants in this project through various decisions and judgments we make in our everyday life. Aesthetics has a surprisingly significant role to play in this regard, though not sufficiently recognized by ourselves or aestheticians. This paper first illustrates how our seemingly innocuous and trivial everyday aesthetic considerations have serious consequences which determine the quality of life and the state of the world, for better or worse. This power of the aesthetic should be harnessed to direct our cumulative and collective enterprise toward better world-making. Against objections to introducing a normative dimension to everyday aesthetics, I argue for the necessity of doing so and draw an analogy between everyday aesthetics and art-centered aesthetics which has dominated modern Western aesthetics discourse.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
45

Roddy, Stephen, and Dermot Furlong. "Embodied Aesthetics in Auditory Display." Organised Sound 19, no. 1 (February 26, 2014): 70–77. http://dx.doi.org/10.1017/s1355771813000423.

Full text
Abstract:
Aesthetics are gaining increasing recognition as an important topic in auditory display. This article looks to embodied cognition to provide an aesthetic framework for auditory display design. It calls for a serious rethinking of the relationship between aesthetics and meaning-making in order to tackle the mapping problem which has resulted from historically positivistic and disembodied approaches within the field. Arguments for an embodied aesthetic framework are presented. An early example is considered and suggestions for further research on the road to an embodied aesthetics are proposed. Finally a closing discussion considers the merits of this approach to solving the mapping problem and designing more intuitively meaningful auditory displays.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
46

Sernelj, Téa. "Different Approaches to Modern Art and Society: Li Zehou versus Xu Fuguan." Asian Studies 8, no. 1 (January 10, 2020): 77–98. http://dx.doi.org/10.4312/as.2020.8.1.77-98.

Full text
Abstract:
Proceeding from the inseparable relation between ethics and aesthetics in traditional (and often also modern) Chinese thought, this article aims to illuminate two important approaches to the aesthetic foundations of Chinese modernity. The relation between the individual and society, which is a core question of modern ethics, is reflected in most of the ethical theories of 20th century China. In this context, the article first presents Li Zehou’s theory of aesthetics and his definition of aesthetic experience. In this way, it aims to illuminate Li’s interpretation of modern art and society, and to posit it into a contrastive position to Xu Fuguan’s ethico-aesthetic theories, especially the ones regarding modernity and Western culture. The basic approaches applied by these two important modern Chinese scholars reveal great differences in attitude towards the spiritual and material development of humanity in the 20th century, which is especially interesting since they are both rooted in the abovementioned belief that ethics cannot be separated from aesthetics. Besides, Li Zehou sincerely admired Xu Fuguan’s work on traditional Chinese aesthetics and referred to his comprehension of general concepts of traditional Chinese aesthetics in many of his own works dealing with aesthetics.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
47

Kranjec, Alexander, and Martin Skov. "Visualizing Aesthetics Across Two Centuries." Empirical Studies of the Arts 39, no. 1 (February 13, 2020): 78–100. http://dx.doi.org/10.1177/0276237420905308.

Full text
Abstract:
Empirical aesthetics is associated with two research questions: How the mind generally assigns value to sensory stimuli and how it responds specifically to art objects. Researchers have debated whether these phenomena share enough to warrant being collapsed into a single field. To ask how these particular questions came to be associated with aesthetics, we conducted Google Ngram analyses over a corpus of books spanning two centuries. Analyses trace the frequency of “big questions” about art and beauty, and how the term aesthetic appears relative to other concepts. Results indicate the 19th century was dominated by notions of beauty and an aesthetic sense. Questions about art and aesthetic experience become more frequent during the 20th century. Results are interpreted with respect to associated affective and evaluative concepts, art movements, and scientific debates. Understanding how aesthetics is used over time can cast light on the ways current work is being conceived and pursued.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
48

Erjavec, Aleš. "Art and aesthetics: Three recent perspectives." SAJ - Serbian Architectural Journal 4, no. 2 (2012): 142–59. http://dx.doi.org/10.5937/saj1202142e.

Full text
Abstract:
The author sketches the development of the relationship between art and aesthetics in the recent past. As his starting point, he takes the position that artists established in the sixties in relation to philosophical aesthetics. In his view 1980 represented a historical threshold as concerns transformations both in art and its philosophy. He then discusses three theories of art and aesthetics - Nicolas Bourriaud's "relational aesthetics" from the nineties, Jacques Rancière's aesthetic project from the following decade, and the very recent "theory of contemporary art" developed by Terry Smith. In author's opinion, these three aesthetic or art theories not only disprove the pervasive opinion that contemporary aesthetics understood as philosophy of art is once more separated from contemporary art and the art world, but also manifest their factual import and impact in contemporary discussions on art.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
49

PŁOTKA, WITOLD. "BEYOND ONTOLOGY: ON BLAUSTEIN’S RECONSIDERATION OF INGARDEN’S AESTHETICS." HORIZON / Fenomenologicheskie issledovanija/ STUDIEN ZUR PHÄNOMENOLOGIE / STUDIES IN PHENOMENOLOGY / ÉTUDES PHÉNOMÉNOLOGIQUES 9, no. 2 (2020): 552–78. http://dx.doi.org/10.21638/2226-5260-2020-9-2-552-578.

Full text
Abstract:
The article addresses the popular reading of Ingarden that his aesthetic theory is determined by ontology. This reading seems to suggest that, firstly, aesthetics lacks its autonomy, and, secondly, the subject of aesthetic experience is reproductive, and passive. The author focuses on Ingarden’s aesthetics formulated by him in the period of 1925–1944. Moreover, the study presents selected elements of Ingarden’s phenomenology of aesthetic experience, and by doing so, the author aims at showing how Ingarden’s aesthetics was reconsidered by Blaustein, a student of Ingarden, whose theory seems to lead one beyond the scope of ontology. Blaustein, namely, reconsiders Ingarden’s theory of purely intentional objects by interpreting it in a descriptive-psychological, or phenomenological fashion. The article is divided into four parts. In section 1, the author highlights historical interconnections between Ingarden, and Blaustein. Section 2.1. is devoted to Ingarden’s phenomenological approach towards aesthetic experience as a phasic structure. At this basis, in section 2.2., Ingarden’s early theory of intentional objects is to be discussed. Section 3 concerns Blaustein’s contribution to phenomenology of aesthetic experience. Given that Blaustein formulates his theory in discussion with Ingarden, section 3.1. is devoted to Blaustein’s critical assessment of Ingarden’s method, and aesthetics. Next, in section 3.2., the author presents Blaustein’s original theory of presentations, and its use in aesthetics. Finally, in section 4, the author lists similarities, and differences between Blaustein’s and Ingarden’s aesthetic theories.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
50

Holt, Matthew. "Ulm Aesthetics." Journal of Design History 33, no. 2 (September 29, 2019): 140–57. http://dx.doi.org/10.1093/jdh/epz038.

Full text
Abstract:
Abstract In order to contribute to the widening and enriching of the notion of aesthetics as it applies to design and so to the historian’s task in this field, this essay examines the theories of aesthetics promulgated at the Hochschule für Gestaltung at Ulm (1953–1968), still a much-understudied institution. In particular, it will investigate the confluence at that school of semiotics and semantics, information aesthetics, and experimental aesthetics. It looks at the break Ulm made with its predecessor, the Bauhaus, on the role of art and aesthetics in design. That break is seen as result of the HfG’s re-evaluation of the profile and substance of industrial design, a re-evaluation itself contingent on an updated understanding of the contemporary ‘environment’ (Umwelt). The article also examines the key aesthetic theories of the figures who passed through Ulm and shaped its curriculum in order to establish the influence of those figures on the wider history of design.
APA, Harvard, Vancouver, ISO, and other styles
We offer discounts on all premium plans for authors whose works are included in thematic literature selections. Contact us to get a unique promo code!

To the bibliography